15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Freedom of Speech 183<br />

16th century, religious war, mutual fratricide, torture,<br />

hatred, and repression had rent the fabric of European society,<br />

which pointed to the increasing incompatibility of<br />

coercing inward belief and outward expression with the<br />

needs of civil and policy society. Further, the consciences<br />

of a growing number of Europeans were moved by the<br />

seeming contrast between the violence of such coercion and<br />

repression, on the one hand, and the claims of religion to be<br />

a source of peace and love, on the other hand. For reasons<br />

of practice and conviction, then, the call for liberty of belief<br />

and expression grew steadily more compelling for those<br />

who saw such spectacle as inconsistent with religion, creating<br />

a growing desire to find ways to live in societies of<br />

more mutual forbearance. The arguments on behalf of that<br />

mutual forbearance, however, led logically and in practice<br />

to freedom of speech being recognized as both a necessity<br />

of our living peacefully together and a moral end in itself.<br />

Many of the calls for religious freedom initially were<br />

meant to apply only within limited but increasingly variegated<br />

communities of belief: to Protestants in general, for<br />

example; or, an extreme latitude at the time, to those who<br />

simply believed in God. As usually occurs with claims for<br />

liberty, however, the spirit of the arguments overflowed the<br />

initial boundaries envisaged. In societies that believed religion<br />

to be mankind’s highest calling and whose members’<br />

greatest pain was occasioned by what they saw as heretical<br />

or impious expressions, winning the debate on behalf of<br />

liberty in religion—the area where restrictions on speech<br />

seemed the most reasonable—carried with it a victory on<br />

behalf of freedom of speech in general.<br />

In the midst of the English Civil War, the Parliamentary<br />

party attempted to censor the book trade by means of the<br />

Licensing Order of 1643. In his Areopagitica, published in<br />

1644, John Milton, although an ardent supporter of the<br />

Parliamentary cause, argued passionately on behalf of<br />

allowing the full force of free debate to sustain both liberty<br />

and truth. Although his opposition to censorship was<br />

intended for good Protestants alone, Milton’s soaring<br />

defense of freedom of expression established more universal<br />

themes. One can choose truth and goodness, he wrote,<br />

only where there is “knowledge of evil”: “I cannot praise a<br />

fugitive and cloistered virtue, unexercised and unbreathed,<br />

that never sallies out and sees her adversary.” Confrontation<br />

with error, he wrote, is essential “to the confirmation of<br />

truth,” and that confrontation depends on “hearing all manner<br />

of reason.” Further, what men possibly could be trusted<br />

to regulate human discourse? When God gave man reason,<br />

Milton urged, “He gave him freedom to choose,” which<br />

made human beings morally responsible. To “know” truth<br />

because of coercion was without merit, and Parliament<br />

would err grievously if it sought, even on behalf of the good,<br />

“to suppress all this flowery crop of knowledge and new<br />

light sprung up and yet springing daily in this city ...to<br />

bring a famine upon our minds again.” Any “free and<br />

humane government” favored “free writing and free speaking.”<br />

Liberty, he wrote, raises the human mind to rare<br />

heights: “Give me the liberty to know, to utter, and to argue<br />

freely according to conscience; above all liberties.” We need<br />

not worry about the strength of truth: “Let her and<br />

Falsehood grapple; who ever knew Truth put to the worse,<br />

in a free and open encounter?” England, he urged, should be<br />

“the mansion house of liberty.”<br />

On the Continent, generations of religious warfare and<br />

persecution led many thinkers to believe that coerced uniformity<br />

and suppression of differences in belief were far more<br />

threatening to both the individual human soul and the stability<br />

and peace of society than diversity of opinion and freedom<br />

of expression. In many of his writings, the great critic,<br />

polemicist, and philosopher Pierre Bayle (1647–1706),<br />

a Huguenot living in exile in Holland after the revocation of<br />

even limited toleration of Protestants in France, argued that<br />

suppression of the outward expression of sincere belief, however<br />

false, corrupted the human spirit, leading men to a<br />

damnable cruelty and hypocrisy. Holland, finely balanced<br />

between Catholics and Protestants, permitted the most freedom<br />

of speech of any nation in Europe by the late 17th century,<br />

out of a prudential concern for what would follow if<br />

various claimants to truth had to fight for control of the state<br />

in order to have liberty of expression. In his Tractatus-<br />

Theologico Politicus (1670), Baruch Spinoza devoted his<br />

final chapter to the proposition that, “in a free commonwealth,<br />

every man may think as he pleases and say what he<br />

thinks.” Because belief was a matter of “individual right . . .<br />

no man may surrender it even if he wishes to do so,” and<br />

governments that sought to compel belief were “tyrannical”<br />

and therefore unstable and subject to violent overthrow. At<br />

the heart of such compulsion was the effort to control expression,<br />

and “the most tyrannical government will be that in<br />

which the individual is denied the freedom to express and to<br />

communicate to others what he thinks.” The function of the<br />

state was not “to transform human beings from rational creatures<br />

into beasts or automatons,” but, to the contrary, “to<br />

enable them to develop their mental and physical faculties in<br />

security” so long as they did not harm others in their liberty<br />

and security. In short, “the purpose of the state is, in actuality,<br />

freedom.”<br />

Shortly after his return to England from exile in<br />

Holland, the philosopher John Locke published A Letter<br />

Concerning Toleration (1689), in which he argued that “It<br />

is one thing to persuade, another to command” and “It is<br />

only light and evidence that can work a change in men’s<br />

opinions.” Locke did not intend that his arguments on<br />

behalf of toleration should apply in particular to atheists or<br />

Catholics, both of whom he believed represented a danger<br />

to the state and society. Yet as with the Declaration of<br />

Independence, whose “all men are created equal” and whose<br />

“life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness” were far from<br />

inclusive claims in the author’s mind, Locke had articulated

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!