15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

184 Freedom of Speech<br />

a principle that had a power to expand human freedom<br />

in general.<br />

The inseparability of the campaign for religious toleration<br />

from the emergence of claims on behalf of freedom of<br />

speech is seen clearly in the American experience, where<br />

the 1st Amendment of the Bill of Rights—ratified in<br />

1791—first established freedom of religion as an essential<br />

right and only then established freedom of speech as such.<br />

Arguing in 1776 on behalf of religious liberty in the<br />

Commonwealth of Virginia, James Madison urged that “the<br />

opinions of men, depending only on the evidence contemplated<br />

by their own minds, cannot follow the dictates of<br />

other men.” Madison’s own bill declared that “all men shall<br />

be free to profess, and by argument to maintain, their opinion<br />

in matters of religion.” With religion considered to be<br />

the most important set of truths, freedom there meant freedom<br />

of expression on virtually all matters of conscience<br />

and importance. Such freedom was, in Madison’s view,<br />

among “the natural rights of mankind,” and, thus, beyond<br />

the reach of any government.<br />

Writing in support of the fullest possible freedom of<br />

belief and expression (absent direct harm to others), the<br />

English philosopher John Stuart Mill wrote in 1859, in his<br />

On Liberty, that, in order to establish freedom of expression,<br />

he would take the most difficult case of all, the right<br />

of those who dissented fundamentally in matters of religion,<br />

because if he could win the issue there, he had won it<br />

for all lesser instances. In making his plea for freedom of<br />

belief and expression, Mill essentially established the pole<br />

toward which both public opinion and jurisprudence gradually,<br />

fitfully, but powerfully would move.<br />

Most people believe that they favor free speech, Mill<br />

argued, but, in fact, almost everyone sets limits at what they<br />

believe to be without value, or dangerous, or just obviously<br />

wrong. Why should we favor freedom of expression even to<br />

what we consider beyond the pale? For Mill, there were<br />

four ultimately compelling reasons, confirmed by history,<br />

for supporting “freedom of opinion, and freedom of the<br />

expression of opinion.” First, the opinion might indeed be<br />

true, and “to deny this is to assume our own infallibility.”<br />

Second, the opinion, although largely or almost wholly in<br />

error, most probably would “contain a portion of truth,” and<br />

censorship would deny us the possible “remainder of the<br />

truth” that only could be gained by “the collision of adverse<br />

opinions.” Third, even if prevailing opinion were the whole<br />

truth, if that truth were not “vigorously and earnestly contested,”<br />

it would be believed by most not on “its rational<br />

grounds,” but only “in the manner of a prejudice.” Only<br />

freedom of expression would permit truth to be embraced<br />

by conviction, not by memorization. Fourth, if people were<br />

not obliged, by liberty of opinion, to defend their beliefs,<br />

truth would be “in danger of being lost, or enfeebled, and<br />

deprived of its vital effect on the character and conduct,”<br />

becoming merely a formula repeated by rote, “inefficacious<br />

for good ...and preventing the growth of any real and<br />

heartfelt conviction, from reason or personal conviction.”<br />

The negative consequences of the suppression of freedom<br />

of speech would fall both on the individual and the society<br />

deprived of strong and daring individuals. In Mill’s celebrated<br />

formulation: “If all mankind minus one were of one<br />

opinion, and only one person were of the contrary opinion,<br />

mankind would be no more justified in silencing that one<br />

person, than he, if he had the power, would be justified in<br />

silencing mankind.”<br />

It was not until the 20th century that the U.S. Supreme<br />

Court, in a set of quite dramatic decisions, brought the<br />

interpretation of the 1st Amendment’s speech clause—<br />

“Congress shall make no law ...abridging the freedom of<br />

speech, or of the press”—closer to Mill’s sense of such<br />

liberty. Originating in cases (and often in minority dissents)<br />

involving the rights of protestors opposed to American participation<br />

in World War I, a line of Supreme Court jurisprudence<br />

vastly broadened the meaning of protected free<br />

speech. In Terminiello v. Chicago (1949), writing for the<br />

Court, Justice William Douglas noted that the<br />

function of free speech under our system of government is<br />

to invite dispute. It may indeed best serve its high purpose<br />

when it induces a condition of unrest, creates dissatisfaction<br />

with conditions as they are, or even stirs people to anger.<br />

In Cohen v. Connecticut (1971), the Court held that<br />

emotively powerful and offensive speech was constitutionally<br />

protected because outrage or anger “may often be the<br />

more important element of the overall message sought to be<br />

communicated.” “One man’s vulgarity,” Justice Marshall<br />

Harlan opined, “is another’s lyric.” In United States v.<br />

Eichman (1990), the Court struck down the Flag Protection<br />

Act of 1989, ruling that, although “desecration of the flag is<br />

deeply offensive to many ...the same might be said ...of<br />

virulent ethnic and religious epithet ...and scurrilous caricatures.”<br />

In a free society, citizens were free, in the absence<br />

of direct harm, to be offensive and scurrilous in each<br />

other’s eyes. In R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul (1992), the Court<br />

invalidated a city ordinance that sought to protect individuals<br />

from expression that “arouses anger, alarm or resentment<br />

on others on the basis of race, color, creed, religion or<br />

gender.” Writing for the Court, Justice Antonin Scalia<br />

stated, “St. Paul has no such authority to license one side<br />

of a debate to fight freestyle, while requiring the other to<br />

follow Marquis of Queensbury rules.”<br />

The Court, however, has never taken the “no law” provision<br />

of the 1st Amendment literally. Obscenity, speech<br />

posing “a clear and present danger” of imminent violence,<br />

and disclosures of information (such as troop or naval<br />

movements) deemed threatening to national security all<br />

remain unprotected. Nonetheless, the Court has brought the<br />

law closer and closer to the spirit of John Stuart Mill’s

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!