15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

340 Montaigne, Michel de (1533–1592)<br />

peculiarities that made him who he was. His focus on the<br />

individual spirit, and the individual voice, was characteristic<br />

of Renaissance humanism. Montaigne’s intense originality<br />

and devotion to the study of the self place him in the<br />

first rank of individualist thinkers.<br />

Montaigne’s individualism did not drift into a dogmatic<br />

egotism, however, and he developed both a humility about<br />

mankind’s limitations and a cosmopolitan attitude toward<br />

the various modes of life he encountered during his travels<br />

throughout Europe. “If it were up to me to train myself in<br />

my own fashion,” he wrote,<br />

there is no way so good that I should want to be fixed in it<br />

and unable to break loose. Life is an uneven, irregular, and<br />

multiform movement. We are not friends to ourselves ...<br />

we are slaves, if we follow ourselves incessantly and are so<br />

caught in our inclinations that we cannot depart from them<br />

or twist them about.<br />

Nor was this an idle boast. Montaigne strongly mistrusted<br />

easy certitudes. Although he was a devout Catholic,<br />

he steadfastly worked for peace between Catholics and<br />

Protestants, a view that set him apart from the vast majority<br />

of his contemporaries. He even went so far as to attempt,<br />

during the worst of the French Wars of Religion, a mediation<br />

between Henri de Guise, leader of the Catholic League,<br />

and Henri de Navarre, the future King Henri IV, who was<br />

still a Protestant. Montaigne was skeptical of the supernatural<br />

in general and particularly of the divine mandate of<br />

government, yet he remained loyal to his faith and to the<br />

French state for fear, he explained, that innovations would<br />

prove worse than the established institutions. In this he was<br />

both a new kind of conservative and a skeptic concerning<br />

the power of human knowledge.<br />

Although he was traditional in his faith and allegiance,<br />

Montaigne abhorred cruelty, torture, and arbitrary rule. He<br />

seldom, if ever, sought to excuse these vices in rulers, and<br />

he often sided with the victims of persecution against their<br />

oppressors. Libertarians are apt to see Montaigne as an intellectual<br />

cousin, and nowhere is this kinship more evident<br />

than in his essay “Of Sumptuary Laws,” where he writes,<br />

The way in which our laws try to regulate ...expenditures<br />

for the table and for clothes seems to be opposed to their<br />

purpose. ...For to say that none but princes shall eat turbot,<br />

or shall be allowed to wear velvet and gold braid, and<br />

to forbid them to the people, what else is this but to give<br />

prestige to these things and increase everyone’s desire to<br />

enjoy them?<br />

Our lack of insight into the minds of others poses a serious<br />

obstacle to any straightforward, systematic attempt to<br />

regulate the conduct of others.<br />

Libertarians are apt to fault Montaigne in one significant<br />

respect—namely, his view of economics. He held that, in<br />

any exchange, one party must gain while another loses. He<br />

appears not to have considered the idea that exchanges<br />

might be mutually beneficial. Ludwig von Mises went so<br />

far as to term this notion the “Montaigne dogma,” and he<br />

devoted a section of his seminal work Human Action to<br />

refuting it. Yet the Montaigne dogma was and remains so<br />

ubiquitous that it may not be wholly fair to assign it to one<br />

individual except insofar as a pervasive fallacy requires a<br />

convenient name.<br />

Although he often appears to be a thinker well ahead of<br />

his time, Montaigne’s upbringing and surroundings seem to<br />

have done much to shape, or at least suggest, his character.<br />

He was born near Bordeaux to a mother of Jewish converso<br />

heritage; three of his siblings would later convert to<br />

Protestantism. A member of the minor nobility, his father<br />

had served in the French army in Italy and developed an<br />

appreciation for humanistic learning. His son Michel was<br />

given peasant godparents and a tutor who spoke no French;<br />

the younger Montaigne spoke only Latin until he was 6<br />

years old. He later made a career in the Parlement of<br />

Bordeaux, where he befriended Étienne de La Boétie and<br />

was among the first to read La Boétie’s Treatise of<br />

Involuntary Servitude, which impressed him deeply.<br />

Montaigne struck up a close friendship with La Boétie,<br />

which ended only at La Boétie’s death.<br />

Considered as a whole, Montaigne’s work presents<br />

something of a paradox. Although he was deeply skeptical<br />

about the ability of any one man or group of men to grasp<br />

absolute truth, still, he manifestly valued the more pedestrian<br />

work of simply trying to understand what one could.<br />

He exhibited remarkable insight into human character at<br />

the individual level, while, by libertarian lights, his understanding<br />

of economic interactions was simplistic.<br />

However, the fact that he had missed the mark might not<br />

have greatly surprised him. Much would always remain<br />

unknown, Montaigne believed, and this fact was to be<br />

accepted with a fortitude that he drew from ancient Stoic<br />

sources.<br />

Libertarians still appreciate Montaigne’s views on the<br />

limits of understanding, inasmuch as many libertarians tend<br />

to view society as a complex interplay of local knowledges<br />

and practices, beyond the ability of any one person or government<br />

to comprehend. In addition, libertarians, following<br />

Montaigne, tend to reject the more ambitious systembuilders<br />

and planners who believe that they can fully master<br />

anything as complex as social institutions or even as<br />

complex as another individual. “I do not see the whole of<br />

anything,” Montaigne wrote, “nor do those who promise to<br />

show it to us.”<br />

See also Humanism; La Boétie, Étienne de; Liberty in the Ancient<br />

World; Republicanism, Classical; Skepticism; Stoicism<br />

JTK

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!