15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

96 Conservative Critique of Libertarianism<br />

libertarian view that “what holds civil society together ...<br />

is self-interest, closely joined to cash payment.” For Kirk,<br />

the market mechanisms appealed to by libertarians necessarily<br />

presuppose a moral framework within which the<br />

members of society view each other as more than merely<br />

potential trading partners with whom they might contract<br />

for mutual benefit. Society, he says—and in this comment<br />

he echoes Burke—“is a community of souls, joining the<br />

dead, the living, and those yet unborn.” This line of thought<br />

has been pursued most systematically in recent years by<br />

Roger Scruton, who argues that the economic, political, and<br />

legal institutions of a free society can function only against<br />

a background of mutual trust between citizens, which<br />

requires a shared sense of membership in a community<br />

defined by social ties and loyalties—religious, ethnic, and<br />

cultural—that run far deeper than considerations of abstract<br />

right and rational self-interest.<br />

Kirk’s fourth objection alleges that libertarians “generally<br />

believe that human nature is good and beneficent,<br />

though damaged by certain social institutions,” contrary to<br />

the conservative view that human nature is imperfect and<br />

imperfectible, at least in this life. Presumably, what Kirk<br />

had in mind here was the kind of celebration of man and of<br />

the power of human reason that one finds in writers like<br />

Ayn Rand, although not all libertarians have put the same<br />

emphasis on this theme that she did. Still there is a tendency<br />

in libertarian thinking to attribute the shortcomings of existing<br />

societies less to individuals than to institutions, especially<br />

governments. Kirk’s fifth line of criticism takes more<br />

direct aim at this attitude, contrasting the libertarian view<br />

that “the state is the great oppressor” with the conservative<br />

view that “the state is natural and necessary for the fulfillment<br />

of human nature and the growth of human civilization.”<br />

This idea is again inherited from the Thomistic<br />

natural law tradition, which regarded the state, no less than<br />

the family and the Church, as a social institution having an<br />

objective nature that does not arise from human convention<br />

or contract.<br />

In the course of making this argument, Kirk also complains<br />

that “libertarians confound the state with government;<br />

in truth, government is the temporary instrument of<br />

the state.” The state, he maintains, is the organic social<br />

whole of which government is but the executive organ,<br />

whose primary function is the restraint of those individual<br />

passions and interests that might threaten the common<br />

good. Some libertarians (such as adherents of the public<br />

choice analysis of governmental action) would object that<br />

government officials are motivated by selfish passions and<br />

interests no less than are private individuals. However, conservatives<br />

tend to argue that in the modern world this fact<br />

holds true largely because of the predominant individualist<br />

ethos, which models all human relations on market transactions<br />

and government on the private firm so that even the<br />

occupants of governmental offices inevitably regard them<br />

as a means of personal advancement. The older ideals of<br />

noblesse oblige and of government as a sacred trust vouchsafed<br />

to men by God for the public interest rather than private<br />

gain were destroyed when the traditional view of the<br />

state as a divinely ordained natural institution gave way to<br />

the classical liberal view of the state as merely a human<br />

artifact created by a social contract entirely for the furtherance<br />

of private interests. From the conservative point of<br />

view, the libertarian critique of the pathologies of the modern<br />

state is analogous to a doctor’s diagnosis of a disease<br />

that he has inflicted on his patient.<br />

Kirk’s final objection to libertarianism is that it “fancies<br />

that this world is a stage for the ego, with its appetites and<br />

self-assertive passions” and eschews the “duty, discipline,<br />

and sacrifice” on which the preservation of society depends.<br />

This view is “impious, in the sense of the old Roman pietas;<br />

that is, the libertarian does not respect ancient beliefs and<br />

customs, or the natural world, or love of country.” These<br />

charges might seem unfair especially because many libertarians<br />

are religious and patriotic. Kirk’s criticism, however, is<br />

presumably directed not at the personal motives of libertarians,<br />

but rather at the implications of their philosophy. What<br />

conservatives tend to object to in libertarianism is its insistence<br />

that we can have no enforceable positive obligations<br />

to others to which we do not explicitly consent. Most conservatives<br />

argue that we actually have many such obligations:<br />

to our parents, children, and other kin; to our country;<br />

and, at least in some circumstances, to those members of<br />

society who are in extreme need. These obligations are not<br />

based on an egalitarian conception of justice, to which conservatives<br />

would object no less vehemently than libertarians<br />

do, but rather on an organic and frankly inegalitarian view<br />

of society in which, to quote a line from Marcus Aurelius<br />

cited by Kirk, “we are made for cooperation, like the hands,<br />

like the feet.” Not all of us have equal honor or equal duties,<br />

but each of us nevertheless plays an irreplaceable role in the<br />

overall social body with the strongest members having, if<br />

not a duty to renounce their strength, at least a duty to use<br />

that strength to help the weakest. Conservatives hold that<br />

this help should come primarily from families, churches,<br />

and other private agencies closest to those in need, but a role<br />

for government, especially at the local level, cannot be dogmatically<br />

ruled out.<br />

Thus, Scruton objects to Nozick’s claim that taxation<br />

amounts to forced labor, holding that “if we are to concede<br />

such an argument, then we abolish the conservative enterprise,<br />

and cease to acknowledge the web of obligations by<br />

which citizens are bound to each other and to the state.” If,<br />

as many conservatives hold, the state is a natural institution<br />

that exists to provide for the common good, then it has a<br />

right to a portion of our income so that it will have the<br />

wherewithal to perform its proper functions. Although conservatives<br />

tend to favor strong private property rights,<br />

many of them regard property as having a social function

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!