15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

106 Corruption<br />

political favors, they would lose confidence in the government.<br />

Thus, contribution limits and other restrictions are<br />

said to bolster confidence in government by mitigating this<br />

appearance of corruption. However, as Nathaniel Persily<br />

discovered, campaign finance appears to have no real relationship<br />

one way or the other to trust in government. In any<br />

case, public trust in government tends to reduce, rather than<br />

protect, individual liberty. Thomas Burke has identified two<br />

other conceptions of corruption in U.S. Supreme Court decisions.<br />

The conception of corruption centering on distortion<br />

assumes that official actions should closely reflect public<br />

opinion: “Campaign contributions are corrupting to the<br />

extent that they do not reflect the balance of public opinion<br />

and thus distort policymaking through their influence on<br />

elections.” The Supreme Court has applied this concept of<br />

distortion to bless state restrictions on political activity by<br />

businesses whose wealth and campaign donations do not<br />

reflect public opinion. The “monetary influence” conception<br />

says public officials are corrupt if they perform their duties<br />

with monetary considerations in mind; sometimes contributions<br />

are said to create political debts that endanger the<br />

integrity of the system. Campaign contributions can thus<br />

corrupt governing even if no explicit deals are made.<br />

Distortion as a corrupt practice assumes that policymaking<br />

should follow public opinion. This idea leaves little<br />

room for constitutional constraints on majorities or for<br />

intense minority views that might one day persuade a<br />

majority. In particular, the illiberal idea that existing public<br />

opinion should provide a standard for limiting participation<br />

in politics enshrines the status quo. Fortunately, this<br />

conception of corruption has been largely ignored by the<br />

Supreme Court. The “monetary influence” conception of<br />

corruption has been joined to ideals of deliberative democracy.<br />

Dennis Thompson argues that representatives should<br />

deliberate about the public good. Private interests are permitted<br />

in a deliberative democracy, but those who advance<br />

them must frame their interests in broader arguments about<br />

the public good. It is argued that money corrupts politics<br />

when contributions enable private interests to make policy<br />

or direct their energies for purely private reasons.<br />

However, campaign donations have a legitimate place in<br />

a liberal republic. They may support speech and other political<br />

activities to advance an ideal of the public good. How<br />

then can citizens or public officials distinguish corrupt and<br />

laudable contributions? The motivations of the giver are<br />

difficult or perhaps impossible to discern, particularly when<br />

purely private interests become skilled at transforming their<br />

self-interest into arguments for the common good. The<br />

deliberative standard seems unworkable, especially given<br />

the important liberties that hang in the balance. Bruce Cain<br />

has objected that deliberative democrats misconstrue the<br />

nature of American politics and thus its corruption or<br />

integrity. The American founders did not create a deliberative<br />

republic in which representatives act as trustees of the<br />

public good. Instead, policymakers aggregate preferences<br />

that citizens reveal through votes, campaign contributions,<br />

voluntary associations, and other ways. The representative<br />

in this pluralist republic is a delegate for the preferences of<br />

his constituents. Apart from bribery, the monetary conception<br />

of corruption makes no sense in this republic; donations<br />

are a weapon in political struggle and a way to better<br />

inform social choices.<br />

Is this conception of pluralism compatible with a liberal<br />

government? Pluralism offers a justification for public<br />

power after constitutional constraints were abrogated with<br />

the New Deal. Groups struggle over policy in a world where<br />

government power over economic life observes few limits.<br />

Pluralists see themselves as the intellectual heirs of James<br />

Madison, but some differences should be noted. Madison<br />

believed in a liberal, constitutional republic in which group<br />

struggle helped sustain the limited nature of the government.<br />

Pluralists recognize no such restraints. Private interests<br />

organize and seek to win in policy struggles. The result can<br />

be rent seeking, which libertarians regard as corruption. Of<br />

course, the organization of groups also may constrain state<br />

power, but the limits here are only partially Madisonian.<br />

Madison’s commitment to constitutions and liberalism has<br />

been lost to most writers who embrace the pluralist conception<br />

of politics. The deliberative democrat seeks to tame private<br />

avarice and abuses of government power through<br />

restrictions on money in politics. Thus, although it is true<br />

that the concerns of pluralists and the deliberative democrats<br />

at times intersect with those of libertarians, both differ in<br />

fundamental ways. As Bradley Smith argues, it is doubtful<br />

that reforms can constrain abuses of power in a postconstitutional<br />

regime like the United States.<br />

Other approaches to corruption exist. Scholars have<br />

recently given much attention to classical republicanism.<br />

Their findings have sometimes deeply contravened liberal<br />

notions. Gordon Wood, for example, writes that “ideally,<br />

republicanism obliterated the individual” in early America.<br />

In recounting the American view of civic virtue in the<br />

1770s, Wood writes of the “willingness of the individual to<br />

sacrifice his private interests for the good of the community.”<br />

Individual liberty in this regard becomes something<br />

akin to corruption of the citizen. Similarly, contemporary<br />

communitarians seem to equate individual liberty with selfishness<br />

and social decline. Such characterizations assume<br />

that any conduct not directed to the common good of a society<br />

must be thought corrupt. This hope for a Spartan regime<br />

has little in common with liberty.<br />

Yet the problem of private interests in politics lingers for<br />

the libertarian. Most libertarians blame the expansion of the<br />

state for corruption. Hence, if we reduce what the government<br />

does, we also will reduce corruption. But if voters are<br />

corrupt in a libertarian sense, liberty may foster corruption<br />

and the expansion of the state. Americans have the liberty<br />

to engage in politics. When they do, they form groups that<br />

seek redistributed wealth for their members or lobby for<br />

restrictions on the liberty of others that would benefit them.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!