15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Rawls, John (1921–2002) 415<br />

Gladstein, Mimi Reisel, and Chris Matthew Sciabarra, eds. Feminist<br />

Interpretations of Ayn Rand. University Park: Pennsylvania State<br />

University Press, 1999.<br />

Rand, Ayn. Atlas Shrugged. New York: Random House, 1957.<br />

———. “Brief Summary.” The Objectivist 10 no. 9 (September<br />

1971): 1–4.<br />

———. Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal. New York: New American<br />

Library, 1967.<br />

———. Letters of Ayn Rand. Michael S. Berliner, ed. Introduction<br />

by Leonard Peikoff. New York: Dutton, 1995.<br />

———. Philosophy: Who Needs It. New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1982.<br />

———. The Virtue of Selfishness: A New Concept of Egoism. New<br />

York: New American Library, 1964.<br />

Sciabarra, Chris Matthew. Ayn Rand: The Russian Radical.<br />

University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995.<br />

———. Ayn Rand: Her Life and Thought. An Atlas Society<br />

Publication. Poughkeepsie, NY: The Objectivist Center, 1999.<br />

RAWLS, JOHN (1921–2002)<br />

John Rawls was perhaps the most prominent and broadly<br />

influential American political philosopher of the 20th century.<br />

Rawls is best known for his 1971 work, A Theory of<br />

Justice, which argues in favor of the institutions of the<br />

modern liberal-democratic welfare state against egalitarian<br />

socialism, on the one hand, and classical liberalism, on the<br />

other hand.<br />

After teaching for a time at Cornell University and the<br />

Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Rawls joined the<br />

philosophy department at Harvard University in 1962 and<br />

remained there for the rest of his long career. During the<br />

1950s, Rawls’s work eschewed a straightforward analysis<br />

of moral concepts, then popular among philosophers, but<br />

instead attempted to describe a general procedure for moral<br />

decision making along Kantian lines. His work also was<br />

informed by contemporary writings in the theory of rational<br />

choice. From the late 1950s to the late 1960s, Rawls published<br />

a series of influential papers that would become the<br />

basis of his most celebrated work, A Theory of Justice.<br />

A Theory of Justice declares that justice is the “first<br />

virtue of social institutions” and seeks to identify those<br />

principles of social organization that will create a “realistic<br />

utopia” in which individuals are free to pursue their ends as<br />

they wish, subject only to constraints that everyone has reason<br />

to accept. According to Rawls, the subject matter of a<br />

theory of justice is the “basic structure” of a society—the<br />

system of interlocking legal, political, economic, and social<br />

institutions that assigns to citizens their fundamental rights<br />

and duties and that determines the terms of social cooperation<br />

and the resulting distribution of opportunities and economic<br />

holdings.<br />

Rawls’s conception of justice, which he dubbed “justice<br />

as fairness,” consists of two related principles of justice.<br />

The “first principle,” intended to set constitutional limits on<br />

democratic government, is essentially a restatement of J. S.<br />

Mill and Herbert Spencer’s principles of equal liberty,<br />

which holds that “each person has an equal right to the most<br />

extensive liberties compatible with similar liberties for all.”<br />

Crucially, however, the liberties Rawls has in mind do not<br />

include those relating to property and contract. The “second<br />

principle,” intended to guarantee the “value” of the basic<br />

liberties he posits, concerns the distribution of opportunities:<br />

wealth, the “social bases of self-respect,” and other<br />

social advantages. He divides this principle into two parts.<br />

The first part, known as the “difference principle,” requires<br />

that “social and economic inequalities are to be arranged<br />

so that they are to be of the greatest benefit to the leastadvantaged<br />

members of society.” The second part requires<br />

that “inequalities attached to offices and positions open to<br />

all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.”<br />

According to Rawls, the first principle is “lexically prior”<br />

to the second, in that inequalities of opportunity and outcome<br />

may not be addressed before a maximally extensive<br />

system of equal liberties has been established and that the<br />

“rearrangement” of these inequalities must take place<br />

within the constraints of the system of liberty.<br />

Rawls attempts to justify his view of “justice as fairness”<br />

and to rule out competing alternatives by recourse to<br />

a kind of “social contract” thought experiment in the tradition<br />

of Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau. However, unlike the<br />

neo-Hobbesian models of rational agency embodied in<br />

standard economic models, Rawls, heavily influenced by<br />

the moral philosophy of Immanuel Kant, depicts people as<br />

distinctly moral agents possessing a “sense of justice” or<br />

“moral capacity” that provides both judgments about<br />

moral matters and motivation to act in accordance with<br />

moral rules, even when this entails the sacrifice of narrow<br />

self-interest. People are understood as rational, in the<br />

economist’s sense, but also as “reasonable.” Rawls’s<br />

thought experiment of choice from the “original position”<br />

is meant to model the way our sense of justice moderates<br />

rational maximization. In the original position, agents are<br />

conceived as maximizing “primary goods”—goods necessary<br />

for the achievement of most any end. But agents also<br />

are conceived as choosing their terms of association from<br />

behind a “veil of ignorance” regarding their talents, opportunities,<br />

economic class, social connections, and so on,<br />

which is meant to model the impartiality and fairness of<br />

reasonable moral beings.<br />

Rawls argues that his two principles of justice are what<br />

agents—so idealized—would choose in the original position.<br />

However, within Rawls’s larger argument, this stands<br />

as only a preliminary justification of his notion of “justice<br />

as fairness.” Principles of justice also must prove stable,<br />

and stability requires that real people would be able to<br />

affirm and comply with them under realistic conditions.<br />

The principles of justice must be in “reflective equilibrium”

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!