15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Conservative Critique of Libertarianism 95<br />

Carey, George W., ed. Freedom and Virtue: The<br />

Conservative/Libertarian Debate. Wilmington, DE:<br />

Intercollegiate Studies Institute, 1998.<br />

Meyer, Frank S. In Defense of Freedom and Related Essays.<br />

Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1996.<br />

Oakeshott, Michael. Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays.<br />

Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1991 [1962].<br />

CONSERVATIVE CRITIQUE<br />

OF LIBERTARIANISM<br />

Libertarianism and conservatism are frequently classified<br />

together as right-wing political philosophies, which is<br />

understandable given the content and history of these<br />

views. Both philosophies are hostile to the egalitarianism<br />

that has motivated socialists and modern liberals and to the<br />

statism with which egalitarians have sought to implement<br />

their program. Edmund Burke, the father of modern conservatism,<br />

was a Whig who sympathized with Adam Smith’s<br />

economics, whereas John Locke, the intellectual ancestor<br />

of natural rights libertarians such as Robert Nozick and<br />

Murray Rothbard, gave his own doctrine of natural rights a<br />

theological foundation. Conservatives in the Anglo-<br />

American tradition have generally tended to follow Burke<br />

in endorsing the free market, and belief in Lockean natural<br />

rights has often been associated with the sort of religious<br />

worldview that most conservatives find congenial.<br />

Accordingly, some conservatives have drawn the conclusion<br />

that libertarianism and conservatism are complementary<br />

tendencies that are best understood as merely different<br />

aspects of the same basic political outlook (e.g., as representing,<br />

respectively, the freedom and order that are both<br />

grounded in the same natural law, and whose unique balance<br />

within Western civilization proves that both are the<br />

inevitable outcome of a process of cultural evolution). The<br />

most influential defender of this fusionist position was<br />

Frank S. Meyer, and his views did much to shape the contemporary<br />

conservative movement. But it also has been<br />

criticized by other conservatives, who tend to regard the<br />

similarities between libertarianism and conservatism as<br />

superficial, masking a deep philosophical divide that makes<br />

the two views ultimately irreconcilable.<br />

Conservatives who hold this view generally regard libertarianism<br />

as merely one utopian modern ideology among<br />

others and as no less beholden to bloodless and rationalistic<br />

abstractions than socialism and fascism, even if the<br />

abstractions (“liberty,” “rights,” and “the market,” rather<br />

than “class,” “race,” or “the people”) are different and less<br />

dangerous. As Michael Oakeshott said disparagingly of<br />

F. A. Hayek’s Road to Serfdom, “a plan to resist all<br />

planning may be better than its opposite, but it belongs<br />

to the same style of politics.” Russell Kirk’s criticism of<br />

libertarianism along similar lines is perhaps best known.<br />

His arguments are stated in, among other places, his essay<br />

“A Dispassionate Assessment of Libertarians” and are representative<br />

of conservative misgivings.<br />

Kirk’s first objection is that libertarians no less than<br />

Marxists deny the existence of the “transcendent moral<br />

order” to which conservatives are committed and “mistake<br />

our ephemeral existence as individuals for the be-all and<br />

end-all.” In response, many libertarians would say that libertarianism<br />

does not necessarily deny that such a moral<br />

order exists, but holds only that it would be wrong and selfdefeating<br />

to attempt to enforce it through the intervention<br />

of government. To do so would interfere with an individual’s<br />

right of self-ownership, respect for which entails<br />

allowing for the possibility that individuals will sometimes<br />

abuse their rights by acting immorally. However, some conservatives<br />

argue that this reply misses the point of Kirk’s<br />

objection. The sort of transcendent moral order Kirk has in<br />

mind, they would say, presumably involves something like<br />

the natural ends or purposes attributed to human beings by<br />

traditional Thomistic natural law theory or God’s ultimate<br />

ownership of human beings as affirmed by Locke in his<br />

version of natural law. This sort of order puts definite constraints<br />

on the kinds of natural rights that human beings can<br />

coherently be said to have because the point of our having<br />

natural rights, according to these theories, is to facilitate the<br />

realization of our natural ends or purposes (according to<br />

traditional Thomists) or to safeguard God’s property<br />

(according to Locke). For traditional Thomistic natural law<br />

theorists, this entails that there can in principle be no right<br />

to do what is contrary to our natural ends or purposes and,<br />

hence, no right to do what is intrinsically immoral (e.g.,<br />

using illicit drugs or viewing pornography). For Locke, it<br />

entails that there can be no right to do what would violate<br />

God’s rights over us (e.g., committing suicide). The thrust<br />

of Kirk’s objection, then, would seem to be that, in insisting<br />

on a right to do many things that traditional natural law<br />

theories, whether Thomist or Lockean, would regard as<br />

immoral, libertarianism implicitly rejects the metaphysical<br />

foundations on which many conservatives take our moral<br />

obligations to rest.<br />

Kirk’s second objection is that order is prior to either<br />

liberty or justice because liberty and justice “may be established<br />

only after order is reasonably secure.” However, he<br />

argues, libertarians “give primacy to an abstract Liberty”<br />

and thereby “imperil the very freedom that they praise.” To<br />

this notion some libertarians reply that Kirk has things<br />

backward: Respect for individual rights to life, liberty, and<br />

property is in their view the foundation of order, because it<br />

makes possible the voluntary transactions out of which<br />

order—whether economic order, or indeed, for some libertarians,<br />

even legal and social order—spontaneously arises<br />

via an “invisible hand” mechanism. This disagreement<br />

brings us to Kirk’s third criticism, which is directed at the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!