15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Retribution for Crime 429<br />

offender a chance to pay were law-breakers. Thus, functioning<br />

legal systems placed primary emphasis on the<br />

right to restitution, rather than to retribution.<br />

In a fully restitution-based system, there would be no<br />

crimes. Their place in the legal order would be filled by<br />

intentional torts (i.e., intentional acts involving the initiation<br />

of force, fraud, or coercion). Only such acts would justify<br />

pursuing restitution from the offender. Such a system<br />

would eliminate from the legal system prosecution of all<br />

“victimless” or “consensual” crimes, such as sodomy, prostitution,<br />

drug consumption, gambling (that is not fraudulently<br />

rigged), and so on. The legal system would no longer<br />

systematically victimize those whose actions do not violate<br />

the rights of others.<br />

Even if the moral and jurisprudential justifications for<br />

restitution offered in Rothbard, Barnett, and Benson are<br />

rejected, there are other reasons that libertarians have traditionally<br />

supported restitution over retribution. Systems of<br />

criminal law tend to generate police abuse and corruption,<br />

whereas the vast majority of crimes against persons go<br />

unreported. Even when reported, most of these crimes<br />

remain unsolved, and a substantial portion that are solved<br />

do not entail punishment that victims find to be satisfactory<br />

or that lead to the rehabilitation of the criminal. Many of<br />

those problems could be alleviated by refocusing the system<br />

on the victim’s right to restitution and the offender’s<br />

responsibility to pay compensation. Relatively cost-effective<br />

(efficient) deterrence would arise as victim reporting<br />

increased, resources were shifted from prosecuting and<br />

punishing victimless crimes, and offenders were more vigorously<br />

pursued and prosecuted. Incentives for actual rehabilitation<br />

of offenders would increase as offenders would<br />

respond to incentives to work off their debts and debt collectors<br />

would seek ways to support that effort. Libertarians<br />

generally believe that liberty, justice, and efficiency are<br />

complementary objectives if the legal system focuses on<br />

the rights of innocent persons not to be victimized and,<br />

should they be, to again be made whole.<br />

See also Common Law; Judiciary; Liability; Retribution for Crime<br />

Further Readings<br />

BLB<br />

Barnett, Randy E. The Structure of Liberty: Justice and the Rule of<br />

Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998.<br />

Benson, Bruce L. The Enterprise of Law: Justice without the State.<br />

San Francisco: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990.<br />

———. To Serve and Protect: Privatization and Community<br />

in Criminal Justice. New York: New York University<br />

Press, 1998.<br />

Bidinotto, Robert J., ed. Criminal Justice? The Legal System vs.<br />

Individual Responsibility. Irvington-on-Hudson, NY: The<br />

Foundation for Economic Education, 1994.<br />

Byock, Jesse L. Viking Age Iceland. New York: Penguin, 2001.<br />

Friedman, David. “Private Creation and Enforcement of Law: A<br />

Historical Case.” Journal of Legal Studies 8 (March 1979):<br />

399–415.<br />

Lyon, Bruce. A Constitutional and Legal History of Medieval<br />

England. 2nd ed. New York: W. W. Norton, 1980.<br />

Peden, Joseph R. “Property Rights in Celtic Irish Law.” Journal of<br />

Libertarian Studies 1 (1977): 81–95.<br />

Pollock, Sir Frederick, and Frederick W. Maitland. The History of<br />

English Law. Washington, DC: Lawyers’ Literary Club, 1959.<br />

RETRIBUTION FOR CRIME<br />

Retributive punishment refers to punishment for a crime that<br />

is carried out for retributive reasons and is justified if there<br />

really are good retributive reasons for punishing crime. To<br />

get a clear sense of this notion, we need to explain what is<br />

meant by crime, punishment, and retribution. Crime has reference<br />

to socially disfavored actions, especially those that<br />

violate rights. Punishment, whether it is spontaneous or part<br />

of a system of law, refers to the imposition of a net loss on<br />

some agent in response to that agent’s performance of some<br />

disfavored action. Punishment is to be distinguished from the<br />

extraction of compensation. If our agent has imposed a loss<br />

on some other party and has in consequence been required to<br />

pay compensation to that party to make up for that loss, he<br />

has not (yet) been subjected to punishment. Punishment is<br />

that additional whack on the head to which our agent is<br />

subjected beyond the extraction of restitution. However, to<br />

explain what retribution is, we need to distinguish between<br />

different sorts of justifications for punishment.<br />

Most of these justifications can be classified as either<br />

consequentialist or retributivist. Consequentialists hold that<br />

punishment is justified by its desirable social results—most<br />

saliently, that punishment acts as a deterrent. Although the<br />

infliction of punishment may be socially undesirable, inflicting<br />

punishment on those who perform criminal actions may<br />

so extensively deter these sorts of actions that the net consequences<br />

of the punishment will be socially optimal. For the<br />

consequentialist, particular punishments or systems of punishment<br />

are justified if, but only if, they tend to be productive<br />

of better overall social outcomes than would be<br />

generated by other punishments or systems of punishment or<br />

would obtain if punishment were abandoned.<br />

In contrast, retributivists insist that, if punishment is<br />

justified, it is justified by considerations of justice, rather<br />

than by its desirable results. Retributivists argue that if the<br />

rationale for punishment is weighed in terms of its socially<br />

optimal results, both punishment of the innocent and<br />

markedly disproportionate punishment of the guilty can be<br />

justified because sometimes punishment of the innocent or<br />

disproportionate punishment of the guilty will have the<br />

optimal social outcome. According to advocates of retribution,<br />

nothing but a primary focus on justice can explain the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!