15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

524 Voluntarism<br />

Further Readings<br />

Aldridge, A. Owen. Voltaire and the Century of Light. Princeton, NJ:<br />

Princeton University Press, 1975.<br />

Durant, Will, and Ariel Durant. The Age of Voltaire: A History of<br />

Civilization in Western Europe from 1715 to 1756. New York:<br />

Simon & Schuster, 1965.<br />

Gay, Peter. Voltaire’s Politics: The Poet as Realist. 2nd ed. New<br />

Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1988.<br />

Knapp, Bettina Liebowitz. Voltaire Revisited. New York: Twayne,<br />

2000.<br />

VOLUNTARISM<br />

Voluntarism—sometimes called philanthropy or charity—<br />

is the donation of money, goods, and time either to those in<br />

need or an otherwise worthy cause.<br />

A question that confronts every society and every political<br />

philosophy concerns our obligations to the poor and<br />

unfortunate and how we are to extend them help. Probably<br />

the most common answer involves an appeal to government<br />

to supply them welfare benefits and other entitlements<br />

financed through taxation. But free-market advocates maintain<br />

that coercing people to assist others is wrong, both<br />

pragmatically and in that it violates others’ rights. Instead,<br />

they appeal to private organizations to provide the necessities<br />

for those in need.<br />

Pragmatically, free-market advocates argue that a taxed<br />

and regulated society is less prosperous with less upward<br />

mobility and thereby experiences poverty; the redistribution<br />

of wealth can be a strong disincentive for people to<br />

earn and so increases the number of people who need help.<br />

Moreover, people who are taxed to underwrite the costs of<br />

welfare are less likely to give voluntarily. The rise of the<br />

welfare state is commonly viewed as the turning point at<br />

which the large-scale philanthropy that marked 19thcentury<br />

society disappeared. If government services were<br />

removed, free-market advocates maintain that people<br />

would be far more likely to voluntarily contribute to charity<br />

and other community causes and in larger amounts. As<br />

evidence, they point to the wide variety of private organizations<br />

that currently exist even in competition with free—<br />

that is, government—assistance.<br />

Those who defend the free market further maintain that,<br />

regardless of whether government best provides for the<br />

poor, coercing such assistance violates individual rights.<br />

As Robert Nozick phrased it, no one has “an enforceable<br />

right”—that is, a legal claim—to assistance from another.<br />

Even a drowning man should not be able to legally compel<br />

aid from people on the shore. Rendering assistance may be<br />

a moral duty, but this notion should not be taken as equivalent<br />

to a legal duty. In many instances, acting within your<br />

rights may be immoral. For example, lying to a friend does<br />

not violate rights, but by most standards is immoral.<br />

Equally, indifference to human suffering does not violate<br />

rights, but may be immoral. Concluding that an action is<br />

moral or immoral does not automatically translate into a call<br />

for the state to either require or punish that action. Indeed,<br />

to demand that all moral duties become legal obligations<br />

would so constrict our lives as to deprive us of all freedom.<br />

Thus, although free-market advocates agree that caring<br />

for the needy is both proper and necessary, they hold on<br />

pragmatic, ethical, and rights-based grounds that these<br />

decisions are ultimately private and must rest with each<br />

individual and his or her conscience.<br />

See also Coercion; Taxation; Welfare State<br />

Further Readings<br />

WME<br />

Machan, Tibor. “Does Libertarianism Imply the Welfare State?” Res<br />

Publica 3 no. 2 (1997): 131–148.<br />

Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic<br />

Books, 1974.<br />

Rand, Ayn. “Government Financing in a Free Society.” The Virtue of<br />

Selfishness. New York: Signet Books, 1964.<br />

VOLUNTARY CONTRACT<br />

ENFORCEMENT<br />

Most people believe that a market economy requires that<br />

governments enforce private contracts. Although some<br />

people may recognize that simple face-to-face trades are<br />

possible without external enforcement, most people argue<br />

that government enforcement is necessary when contracts<br />

are complicated, include commitments over time, or<br />

involve large groups. In many real-world situations, however,<br />

enforcement of contracts by public courts is too<br />

costly—government courts are not perfect, after all—or<br />

impossible, inasmuch as government courts often lack<br />

jurisdiction across political boundaries or the desire to<br />

enforce contracts in sectors not sanctioned by law. The private<br />

sector, in contrast, has found numerous ways to promote<br />

contractual performance even when government<br />

enforcement is absent. From the discipline of continuous<br />

dealings in small groups, to reputation mechanisms or more<br />

formal private tribunals for large groups, numerous devices<br />

have emerged that have made possible contractual performance<br />

independent of government. Recognizing that<br />

private parties can overcome the potential problem of contractual<br />

performance brings into question whether government<br />

enforcement of contracts is necessary. This topic is of<br />

growing interest to libertarians.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!