15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Progress 397<br />

and desirable direction, and infers that this progress will<br />

continue indefinitely.” Bury contends that progress, in this<br />

sense, is a distinctively modern notion—one that does not<br />

begin to take shape until the 16th and 17th centuries,<br />

whereas other historians, such as Robert Nisbet, attribute<br />

the idea to Greek, Roman, and Christian writers long before<br />

the advent of the modern era.<br />

A libertarian theory of progress is one that stresses<br />

the role of liberty in the progressive improvement of<br />

humankind. Whatever position we may take in the historical<br />

controversies about the origin of the idea of progress<br />

and its relationship to other ideas (such as the belief in an<br />

Arcadian golden age, original sin, and divine providence),<br />

there can be little doubt that the link between individual<br />

freedom and progress was forged by post-Renaissance<br />

philosophers, historians, economists, and social theorists.<br />

In The Idea of Progress, Bury divides modern theories<br />

of progress into two types, which he characterizes as socialist<br />

and liberal. The socialist version he describes as “a symmetrical<br />

system in which the authority of the state is<br />

preponderant, and the individual has little more value than<br />

a cog in a well-oiled wheel: his place is assigned; it is not<br />

his right to go his own way.” Liberalism, in contrast, views<br />

individual freedom and social diversity as essential to<br />

progress. Unlike the closed system of socialism, in which<br />

the ultimate goal of progress is foreseeable, having been<br />

mapped out in advance by central planners, classical liberalism<br />

was historically affiliated with a theory known as<br />

“indefinite progress.” In this approach, no limits can be set<br />

to progress, nor can we predict the exact path or form that<br />

progress will take. “Individual liberty is the motive force”<br />

of indefinite progress, and this decentralized, spontaneous<br />

process generates rapid innovations that cannot be predicted<br />

or controlled by any individual, group, or institution,<br />

including government.<br />

Theories of progress are typically concerned with three<br />

spheres of human activity: intellectual, moral, and economic.<br />

Libertarian theories of intellectual progress emerged<br />

during the 17th century, as John Milton, Benedict Spinoza,<br />

and John Locke, among others, argued that freedom of<br />

thought, discussion, and publication are essential to the<br />

advancement of knowledge. Often grouped under the collective<br />

label of “liberty of conscience,” these freedoms<br />

came to be widely accepted as indispensable to the pursuit<br />

of truth in religion, science, and other spheres, and they<br />

played a crucial role in the struggle for religious toleration.<br />

We do not find this near-unanimity, even among libertarian<br />

thinkers, on the subject of moral progress. It has<br />

often been pointed out that knowledge can be used for good<br />

or evil purposes, and some liberals, such as Adam Ferguson<br />

and Joseph Priestley, warned against the enervating effects<br />

of luxury and other vices, which they believed would lead<br />

to the corruption of those moral virtues necessary to sustain<br />

a free society. Other liberals disagreed. In the writings of<br />

David Hume, Edward Gibbon, Adam Smith, and others, we<br />

see various arguments in defense of luxury and other personal<br />

vices (i.e., those that do not violate the rights of others)<br />

based largely on their unintended, but beneficial,<br />

consequences to society as a whole. Many of these arguments<br />

are variations on a theme first presented by the Dutch<br />

philosopher Bernard Mandeville in his notorious book, The<br />

Fable of the Bees: Or, Private Vices, Publick Benefits, first<br />

published in 1705 as The Grumbling Hive and greatly<br />

expanded in subsequent editions.<br />

Another internal debate among classical liberals<br />

addressed the possibility of moral progress, a topic that<br />

received a good deal of attention during the 19th century.<br />

W. E. H. Lecky, J. S. Mill, Herbert Spencer, and many other<br />

liberals maintained that progress in the moral sphere (especially<br />

the “sentiment of justice”) is as evident in the historical<br />

record as any other kind of progress, and they point to<br />

advances in religious toleration, the repudiation of torture,<br />

and the abolition of slavery to buttress their case. But other<br />

liberals, most notably H. T. Buckle and others influenced<br />

by the positivistic sociology of Auguste Comte, presented a<br />

different analysis.<br />

In the first volume of his best-selling Introduction to the<br />

History of Civilization in England (1857), Buckle defends<br />

the thesis that moral sentiments and motives, unlike knowledge,<br />

are “stationary” and do not progress from one generation<br />

to the next. As Buckle put it, “the sole essentials of<br />

morals...have been known for thousands of years, and not<br />

one jot or tittle has been added to them by all the sermons,<br />

homilies, and text-books which moralists and theologians<br />

have been able to produce.” True progress occurs in the<br />

realm of knowledge as people become more cognizant of<br />

the long-range consequences of their decisions and actions.<br />

Perhaps the most important contribution of libertarian<br />

thinkers was in the sphere of economic progress. The<br />

growth of commerce, or what was sometimes called the<br />

commercial spirit, was widely regarded by liberals as a<br />

lynchpin of socioeconomic progress.<br />

In Book III of The Wealth of Nations, Adam Smith discusses<br />

“the natural progress of opulence.” The motive of<br />

self-interest, when confined within the sphere of justice,<br />

naturally leads to a division of labor that is “advantageous<br />

to all the different persons employed in the various occupations.”<br />

This natural economic order—which develops spontaneously,<br />

without foresight or central planning—is called<br />

natural because it is “promoted by the natural inclinations<br />

of men” in a “system of natural liberty,” in which the equal<br />

rights of every individual to life, liberty, and property are<br />

secured by a just system of law and government.<br />

Free-market liberals agreed with Montesquieu that the<br />

“natural effect of commerce is to lead to peace” because<br />

trade creates a mutual dependence among nations, and “all<br />

unions are founded on mutual needs.” Progress, in this<br />

view, is best achieved during periods of peace.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!