22.03.2013 Views

Seeing clearly: Frame Semantic, Psycholinguistic, and Cross ...

Seeing clearly: Frame Semantic, Psycholinguistic, and Cross ...

Seeing clearly: Frame Semantic, Psycholinguistic, and Cross ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION 8<br />

rather, we expect to nd connections between them based on general cognitive principles.<br />

For example, we expect that people will often classify things <strong>and</strong> events on the basis of<br />

perceived similarity, <strong>and</strong> that to a large extent, people will agree on those similarities <strong>and</strong><br />

those classi cations. As Lako (1987:Ch. 6) has shown, the basis of the classi cation can<br />

be quite complex, but it is not completely arbitrary. Wide-ranging psychological results<br />

have also shown that certain types of categorization are more basic than others, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

the tendency of certain events to co-occur is one of the bases of such categorization.<br />

Category Structure <strong>and</strong> Gradation<br />

Questions about the adequacy of Aristotelian de nitions have also raised questions<br />

about the assumptions on which they are based, such as the \Law of the Excluded Middle",<br />

which says that for any set X, any individual must be either in or out of the set. If X<br />

represents the set of things having the attribute A, then we cansay that any individual<br />

must be either A or not A; philosophers have spilled a lot of ink over what to do about<br />

cases in which an attribute seems to be neither true nor false of an individual, but simply<br />

inapplicable, e.g. is the number 3 blue or not?<br />

A new spurt of interest in these questions began in the 1970s with the research<br />

of Eleanor Rosch <strong>and</strong> her associates. They found that for many types of categories, it was<br />

possible to measure not just whether or not an instance was a member of the category, but<br />

whether or not the instance was a \good example" of the category; these judgements of<br />

whether an instance is a better or worse example of a category have been called \represen-<br />

tativeness", \exemplariness", \graded category structure", <strong>and</strong> \prototype e ects"; I will<br />

use the last term. Prototype e ects have been found to be very robust <strong>and</strong> to be manifest<br />

in a variety of measures (Rosch 1978; Rosch in press).<br />

There was an initial burst of excitement after the rst discovery of prototype e ects<br />

in which itwas assumed that they were a direct re ection of the mental representation<br />

of the concept. It was gradually discovered that this was incorrect, but this fallacious<br />

interpretation of the data has plagued the eld ever since. Lako (1987:136 .) claims that<br />

the error arises from two incorrect interpretations of e ects: (1) E ects = Structure <strong>and</strong><br />

(2) Prototype = Representation. The former assumes that if there is variation in ratings of<br />

\goodness of example" over a group of items that this means that the category in question

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!