22.03.2013 Views

Seeing clearly: Frame Semantic, Psycholinguistic, and Cross ...

Seeing clearly: Frame Semantic, Psycholinguistic, and Cross ...

Seeing clearly: Frame Semantic, Psycholinguistic, and Cross ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION 37<br />

meaning of see asasingleword.<br />

In this dissertation, I will adopt a position between these extremes. One could<br />

suppose that there are simply several verbs to see in English, i.e. that there is not only<br />

homonymy between the noun see <strong>and</strong> the verb see but among the several verbs as well. But<br />

that would be odd, since all the senses of see are related to the \same" lexeme, e.g. all of<br />

them have the same irregular past <strong>and</strong> past participle forms.<br />

There are cases of verbs which seem to be related in meaning but are in ected<br />

di erently, (e.g. They hung the picture vs. They hanged the rustler); that this does not<br />

happen with see argues for fundamental unity on morphological grounds. On semantic<br />

grounds, we nd considerable overlap of meaning among the senses, but no simple set of<br />

necessary <strong>and</strong> su cient criteria for all of them.<br />

It therefore seems logical to claim that the word see is polysemous (that it has<br />

more than one sense), <strong>and</strong> that at least the majority of its senses are related in meaningful<br />

ways that make it easier to learn the entire constellation of senses.<br />

Throughout most of this dissertation, the vexed question of what is a separate<br />

sense <strong>and</strong> what is merely a speci c use of a more general sense will be dealt with only<br />

in passing. Instead, the aim will be to look for the nest distinctions which seem to be<br />

justi ed, <strong>and</strong>, near the end, to try to reach some conclusions about which deserve the<br />

status of separate senses <strong>and</strong> which can be grouped together.<br />

In other words, I will assume that \. . . di erent constructions are typically, possibly<br />

always, accompanied by slightly di erent semantic interpretations. . . " (Goldberg 1995:8)<br />

This principle is familiar from the diachronic point of view; whenever language changes so<br />

that there are two competing forms in the same general semantic domain, speakers tend<br />

to associate some (possibly novel) semantic distinction with the di erence in form. This<br />

accounts for the well-known fact that there are rarely or never any exact synonyms in a<br />

language (Cruse 1986:265-270), but does not imply that there is one <strong>and</strong> only one sense per<br />

grammatical form|the pairing actually seems to be many-to-many, aswe will see below.<br />

Methodological Note<br />

Despite the admitted importance of the larger linguistic <strong>and</strong> non-linguistic context,<br />

I will for the most part consider sentences in isolation in the manner of many traditional<br />

linguistic analyses; if we believe that the meaning of a sentence is derivable from the mean-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!