19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

the contradictions <strong>of</strong> premodernity 147<br />

their claims leave considerable room for disagreement. Erasmus clearly<br />

prefers the earlier anti-Manichean Augustine and Luther the later anti-<br />

Pelagian Augustine, but neither stops there. Erasmus, like his humanist<br />

predecessors, wants to interpret the earlier Augustine’s notion <strong>of</strong> the free<br />

will in a Neoplatonic fashion, drawing on church fathers such as Origen<br />

and Jerome. He also adopts a skeptical position on matters open to interpretation<br />

and employs a skeptical strategy in his attempts to draw Luther into<br />

discussion. Luther, by contrast, does not rely on the other church fathers<br />

or on any philosopher for support but turns instead to Scripture, which in<br />

his view speaks directly and indubitably to the individual Christian. His<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> Scripture and his assertion <strong>of</strong> its absolute certainty, however,<br />

are essentially Stoic. 45 Similarly, he resists being drawn into a discussion<br />

and insists upon a more judicial proceeding because he understands the<br />

skeptical trap that Erasmus has set for him. He also recognizes Erasmus’s<br />

attempt to make use <strong>of</strong> this earlier debate to portray himself as a moderate,<br />

but he is convinced that Erasmus is disingenuous, concealing his true<br />

Pelagian position. He seeks to bring this out in his response. In light <strong>of</strong> the<br />

position Luther takes in Bondage <strong>of</strong> the Will, Erasmus comes to believe that<br />

Luther is not merely a Stoicizing Augustinian but a Manichean, a fatalist,<br />

and an antinomian. Each thus tries to occupy an Augustinian position,<br />

modifi ed somewhat in one direction or the other. Each, however, also suspects<br />

that the other is disingenuously trying to portray himself as more<br />

moderate than he actually is, and in their ripostes each thus portrays the<br />

other as more radical than he actually was.<br />

erasmus’s diatribe<br />

Th e debate began with the publication <strong>of</strong> Erasmus’s On the Free Will: Diatribe<br />

or Discussion. As its title suggests, the work is a diatribe, which classically<br />

is a form <strong>of</strong> deliberative and not epidictic rhetoric, thus not a form<br />

<strong>of</strong> attack but <strong>of</strong> discussion. 46 Erasmus adopts this mode in part to derail<br />

the public inquisition <strong>of</strong> Luther, but also in an eff ort to turn the matter in<br />

a more philosophical direction. 47 Substantively, Erasmus seeks to engage<br />

Luther on the issue that lies at the heart <strong>of</strong> his diff erences with the humanists<br />

and in a very real sense at the heart <strong>of</strong> Christianity—the question <strong>of</strong><br />

the relationship <strong>of</strong> the divine and human wills. 48<br />

Erasmus begins by stating that he does not want to engage in a debate<br />

and prefers instead a friendly discussion about a question that he himself<br />

fi nds very puzzling, the question <strong>of</strong> free will. Th is beginning, as Luther and<br />

many others have recognized, is disingenuous, an example <strong>of</strong> the Socratic

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!