19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

246 chapter seven<br />

religious view <strong>of</strong> good and evil, its justifi cation lies not in religion in the<br />

narrow sense but in the laws <strong>of</strong> nature which are not just for a particular<br />

people but for all human beings, based upon the universal human desire<br />

for self-preservation and aimed at eliminating the “great enemy <strong>of</strong> nature,”<br />

that is, violent death. 122 Th ese laws spell out a justifi cation for obedience to<br />

the sovereign rooted in nature. Th ey explain why any sovereign who does<br />

rule should be obeyed, and not how a sovereign comes to rule.<br />

Th e law <strong>of</strong> nature, which is the foundation <strong>of</strong> this science, follows from<br />

these premises. If this law were simply the result <strong>of</strong> introspection, it would<br />

at best be a prudent suggestion. Its obligatory character, however, follows<br />

from the fact that it is not merely rooted in nature but is the embedded<br />

command <strong>of</strong> nature’s God. 123 We may fi nd this idea strange because we<br />

imagine obligation to arise only from situations in which we have freely<br />

given our consent. For Hobbes, however, there is nothing that is freely<br />

given in an absolute sense. Everything we do, we do because we are in a<br />

real sense pushed to do it. Obligation thus is not something chosen but<br />

something imposed as a result <strong>of</strong> an unequal power relationship. We are<br />

thus obliged only because we are commanded. 124<br />

hobbes’ theology<br />

While Hobbes was convinced that human beings could eliminate violent<br />

death in a commonwealth ruled by an absolute sovereign, he also knew<br />

that death itself was inevitable. Descartes had suggested in the Discourse<br />

that science might eventually overcome death and indefi nitely extend human<br />

life, but Hobbes was under no such illusions. Moreover, he knew that<br />

the fear <strong>of</strong> death inevitably led to questions about the aft erlife, and that<br />

such questions posed tremendous problems for political stability since the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> gaining eternal life in some cases could outweigh the desire<br />

to preserve this life. Th e proclamations <strong>of</strong> priests and the delusions <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

fanatics about the nature <strong>of</strong> good and evil thus could become more<br />

compelling than the commands <strong>of</strong> the sovereign and throw the state into<br />

chaos. Th e Wars <strong>of</strong> Religion in his view were the result <strong>of</strong> such a state <strong>of</strong><br />

aff airs, and the only way to avoid this problem was for the sovereign to rule<br />

both the church and the state. 125<br />

While both <strong>of</strong>fi ces must be united, Hobbes did not favor a theocracy. In<br />

fact, the rule <strong>of</strong> priests with exclusive intercessionary powers or <strong>of</strong> inspired<br />

saints was exactly what he feared. Such theocratic impulses in his view can<br />

only be quelled by granting the civil sovereign both temporal and ecclesiastical<br />

dominion. However, this solution, which is known as Erastianism,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!