19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the contradictions <strong>of</strong> enlightenment 259<br />

proceed freely in this direction. . . . Th e inclination to and vocation for free<br />

thinking . . . fi nally even infl uences the principles <strong>of</strong> government, which<br />

fi nds that it can pr<strong>of</strong>i t by treating men, who are now more than machines,<br />

in accord with their dignity.” 11<br />

While Kant perhaps never doubted that universal enlightenment and<br />

the rule <strong>of</strong> reason could be attained, he recognized, especially from his<br />

reading <strong>of</strong> Hume, that there were powerful reasons to doubt that the notion<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason that modern thinkers employed could provide the foundation<br />

for the two great goals <strong>of</strong> modern thought, the mastery <strong>of</strong> nature<br />

through modern science and the realization <strong>of</strong> human freedom. Th ese<br />

doubts arose from the fact that reason itself seemed inevitably and ineluctably<br />

to become entangled in aporiae and contradiction. Th ese aporiae or,<br />

as Kant called them, antinomies, threatened to undermine the modern<br />

project <strong>of</strong> mathesis universalis and leave humanity lost in the abyss <strong>of</strong><br />

Humean skepticism.<br />

Kant fi rst considered the problem <strong>of</strong> the antinomies in his dissertation<br />

(1770), he but did not appreciate their full signifi cance until aft er reading<br />

Hume. In the period before he began writing the Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason<br />

(published in 1781), he came to understand their deeper signifi cance. He<br />

explained this in a letter to Garve on September 26, 1798, asserting that<br />

it was “not the investigation <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> God, <strong>of</strong> immorality, etc.<br />

but the antinomy <strong>of</strong> pure reason . . . from which I began. : ‘Th e world has<br />

a beginning—:it has no beginning, etc., to the fourth [?] Th ere is freedom<br />

in human being,—against there is no freedom and everything is natural<br />

necessity’; it was this that fi rst woke me from my dogmatic slumber and<br />

drove me to the critique <strong>of</strong> reason itself to dissolve the scandal <strong>of</strong> the contradiction<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason with itself.” 12 Th e central reference here is to the Th ird<br />

Antinomy (the seventy-four year old Kant misspeaks himself in his reference<br />

to the Fourth Antinomy). Th is antinomy purports to show that it is<br />

impossible to give a meaningful causal explanation <strong>of</strong> the whole without<br />

the assumption <strong>of</strong> a fi rst cause through freedom, and yet that the very possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> such freedom undermines the necessity <strong>of</strong> any causal explanation.<br />

13 In other words, modern natural science, which analyzes all motion<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> effi cient causes, is unintelligible without a freely acting fi rst<br />

cause such as God or man, but such causality through freedom, which<br />

is essential to morality, is incompatible with natural necessity. Freedom<br />

is thus both necessary to causality and incompatible with it. Kant recognized<br />

that if this conclusion were correct, the modern project was selfcontradictory<br />

and that modern reason could give man neither the mastery<br />

<strong>of</strong> nature nor the freedom that he so desired.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!