19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

346 notes to pages 231–234<br />

Martinich, Hobbes, 191. Damrosch argues in a related vein that Hobbes’ God is a<br />

deus absconditus with a vengeance. Th e Reformation in his view stressed God’s<br />

ever-present power, Hobbes his divine remoteness. “Hobbes as Reformation<br />

Th eologian,” 346.<br />

79. On this point see Tuck, “Hobbes and Descartes,” in Perspectives on Th omas<br />

Hobbes, 13–40; as well as Amos Funkenstein, Th eology and the Scientifi c Imagination<br />

from the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton<br />

University Press, 1986), 80–86. As we will see, Hobbes also believes that we are<br />

directed toward this science by the insight God gives us.<br />

80. EW, 1:17.<br />

81. For Hobbes, theory that cannot be practiced has no value. Martinich, Hobbes, 91.<br />

82. Tuck, “Hobbes and Descartes,” 30.<br />

83. Ibid., 31.<br />

84. According to Ted Miller, Hobbes believes we reason by true fi ctions, but the purpose<br />

<strong>of</strong> reasoning is to make the fi ctions come true. “Th omas Hobbes and the<br />

Constraints that Enable the Imitation <strong>of</strong> God,” Inquiry 42, no. 2 (June, 1999): 160.<br />

85. Elizabeth Brient has argued that theological voluntarism humbled human epistemological<br />

pretension, so that hypothesis rather than theoria emerged as the<br />

appropriate attitude when faced with the mute facticity <strong>of</strong> nature. “From Vita<br />

Contemplativa to Vita Activa: Modern Instrumentalization <strong>of</strong> Th eory and the<br />

Problem <strong>of</strong> Measurement,” International Journal <strong>of</strong> Philosophical Studies 9, no. 1<br />

(2001): 23.<br />

86. Like the natural world, this new one is created by the word. Hobbes, Leviathan,<br />

280. Hobbes urges readers to imitate God, but he also suggests we can become<br />

more dignifi ed by creating something new. Miller, “Th omas Hobbes and the Constraints,”<br />

163.<br />

87. Mersenne, “Ballistica,” in Th omas Hobbes Malmesburiensis opera philosophica<br />

quae latine scripsit omnia, ed. Guliemi Molesworth, 5 vols. (London: Bohn, 1839–<br />

45), 5:309. Th e summary <strong>of</strong> Hobbes’ work in the Meresenne essay was almost certainly<br />

composed by Hobbes himself.<br />

88. Ibid., 5:315.<br />

89. EW, 1:91–92.<br />

90. De Corpore, EW 1: 91–92.<br />

91. Ibid., 1:1.<br />

92. Ibid., 1:66.<br />

93. Martinich points out that Hobbes is unwilling to subordinate geometry to arithmetic,<br />

because he believes knowledge must be reducible to sensation. Th us numbers<br />

have no independent reality and are merely names <strong>of</strong> points. Martinich,<br />

Hobbes, 284.<br />

94. Hobbes’ truths thus take a hypothetical form, but the connections they specify<br />

are necessary. Hobbes believes, for example, that, “If x occurs, then y necessarily<br />

follows.” Th is diff ers from the claim that the historian makes, which takes the<br />

form, “When x occurred, y followed.” Obviously, the same event may occur in<br />

the future under similar circumstances, but a great deal depends on how similar

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!