19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

260 chapter eight<br />

Kant’s philosophical enterprise aimed at resolving the problem posed<br />

by the antinomies. 14 Th e antinomies, as Kant sees them, are only apparent<br />

and not real contradictions. Th ey arise as the consequence <strong>of</strong> an attempt<br />

by the understanding (which deals only with fi nite things) to grasp the infi<br />

nite. In struggling to understand what it cannot understand, it inevitably<br />

falls into perplexity. Kant believes we can solve the problem <strong>of</strong> the antinomies<br />

by recognizing and accepting the limits <strong>of</strong> our rational capacities.<br />

We must, in other words, confi ne the understanding to its native realm, to<br />

what Kant calls “the island <strong>of</strong> truth,” and resist the lure <strong>of</strong> a fatal voyage in<br />

search <strong>of</strong> the infi nite on the foggy, iceberg-infested seas that surround this<br />

island. Th e critique <strong>of</strong> reason that establishes these limits is thus an eff ort<br />

to know oneself and hence an integral moment <strong>of</strong> enlightenment. What<br />

Kant believes he can show through such a critique is that reason “knows”<br />

in two diff erent ways: fi rst, through the understanding (pure reason),<br />

which gives us a scientifi c (and causal) account <strong>of</strong> existence, and second,<br />

through a moral sense (practical reason) rooted in our transcendental freedom,<br />

which tells us what is right and wrong. Th e apparent contradiction<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason with itself is thus the consequence not <strong>of</strong> the contradictory character<br />

<strong>of</strong> existence or the inadequacy <strong>of</strong> reason but <strong>of</strong> the misuse <strong>of</strong> reason.<br />

Th e correct use <strong>of</strong> reason, Kant believes, will make possible the mastery <strong>of</strong><br />

nature and attainment <strong>of</strong> human freedom, which will produce prosperity<br />

and morality and consequently political liberty and perpetual peace. Kant<br />

thus believed that transcendental idealism could save the modern project<br />

by providing the philosophical ground for the reconciliation <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

and science, and that it would thus make possible the continued growth in<br />

enlightenment and human progress.<br />

Th is “solution,” however, was not universally accepted, largely because<br />

Kant did not, and perhaps could not, explain how the two faculties <strong>of</strong><br />

knowing, pure and practical reason, could be conjoined in consciousness.<br />

15 Kant recognized that this was a problem and argued that these two<br />

capacities were unifi ed in the transcendental unity <strong>of</strong> apperception (or<br />

self-consciousness), but he did not explain how such a unity was possible.<br />

Rather he simply asserted that without such a unity experience would be<br />

impossible. Since we do have experience, he concluded that such a unity<br />

must exist. However, to many <strong>of</strong> his immediate successors it seemed as if<br />

Kant had not solved the problem <strong>of</strong> the antinomies but displaced it, saving<br />

science and morality only by making self-consciousness itself unintelligible.<br />

Nineteenth- and twentieth-century continental thought is in large<br />

measure a series <strong>of</strong> attempts to come to terms with the question that Kant<br />

posed in the antinomies, that he himself failed to adequately answer, and<br />

that was driven home by the French Revolution.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!