19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

petrarch and the invention <strong>of</strong> individuality 67<br />

Th ough our ultimate goal does not lie in virtue, where the philosophers locate<br />

it, it is through the virtues that the direct way leads to the place where it<br />

does lie; and these virtues, I must add, must be not merely known but loved.<br />

Th erefore, the true moral philosophers and useful teachers <strong>of</strong> the virtues are<br />

those whose fi rst and last intention is to make hearer and reader good, those<br />

who do not merely teach what virtue and vice are . . . but sow into our hearts<br />

love <strong>of</strong> the best and eager desire for it and at the same time hatred <strong>of</strong> the<br />

worst and how to fl ee it. It is safer to strive for a good and pious will than for<br />

a capable and clear intellect. Th e object <strong>of</strong> the will . . . is to be good; that <strong>of</strong><br />

the intellect is truth. It is better to will the good than to know the truth. . . .<br />

In this life it is impossible to know God in His fullness; piously and ardently<br />

to love Him is possible . . . [as it is] to know that virtue is the next best thing<br />

to God himself. When we know this, we shall love him for his sake with our<br />

heart and marrows, and virtue we shall love for His sake too. 165<br />

On its surface, this view seems very pious, but it does not live up to Jesus’<br />

two commandments. Petrarch does not suggest that we follow divine<br />

commands, that we love our neighbor, or that we lead a life <strong>of</strong> poverty and<br />

ascetic denial. Still, he also does not fall into either an Epicureanism or<br />

Stoicism that is centered completely on man. 166 He continues to praise the<br />

classical life <strong>of</strong> virtue, the value <strong>of</strong> friends, and the necessity <strong>of</strong> leisure, but<br />

he praises them not in their own right but because it is pleasing to God<br />

and is the road to our immortality. Th e highest Christian possibility, for<br />

Petrarch, thus looks remarkably like the life <strong>of</strong> the philosophic sage and<br />

decidedly unlike that <strong>of</strong> the saint or the martyr. Petrarch mentions the<br />

example <strong>of</strong> Socrates only rarely, but it is clearly something like the life <strong>of</strong><br />

Socrates that he has in mind. Th us, in his view we come to understand our<br />

duty not through Scripture or the works <strong>of</strong> the Fathers, but through an<br />

introspective self-examination. “Conscience,” Petrarch tells us, “is the best<br />

judge <strong>of</strong> virtue.” 167 It is the witness that tells us what is right. 168 Coming<br />

to terms with this voice may include the reading <strong>of</strong> Scripture (along with<br />

Cicero, Seneca, et al.), but it ultimately depends upon the kind <strong>of</strong> critical<br />

self-examination Petrarch undertook in My Secret and the withdrawal<br />

from public life that he described in Th e Solitary Life.<br />

Petrarch thus neither sets man up to rival God nor deprives man <strong>of</strong> God.<br />

Rather, he seeks to combine Christianity with the notion <strong>of</strong> virtue he fi nds<br />

in Cicero and Seneca. All <strong>of</strong> this is enclosed within a notion <strong>of</strong> individuality<br />

that is prefi gured in if not derived from nominalism. To put the matter<br />

more generally, Petrarch seeks a synthesis <strong>of</strong> Augustinianism that emphasizes<br />

man’s dependence on his creator with a Stoicism that emphasizes his

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!