19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the contradictions <strong>of</strong> enlightenment 275<br />

than the sinful viator <strong>of</strong> Christianity or the rational animal <strong>of</strong> antiquity.<br />

Building on the earlier work <strong>of</strong> Descartes (who himself drew on the humanist<br />

tradition), Malebranche argued that in contemplating ideas and<br />

eternal truths the human mind participates in God. Leibniz made a similar<br />

claim in his monadology, imagining in Neoplatonic fashion that human<br />

being participated in or was an emanation <strong>of</strong> divine being. Many<br />

Enlightenment thinkers, however, were convinced that such views did not<br />

go far enough. Th ey believed that one could only truly understand human<br />

being if it was completely freed from the tyranny <strong>of</strong> God and the church.<br />

Religion fi lled the world with so many imaginary entities and powers that<br />

under its sway human beings could not comprehend what was distinctive<br />

and valuable about their own being. Lamettrie argued that humans could<br />

not come to terms with themselves or be happy as long as they believed<br />

in God. In his view man is a natural being and must understand himself<br />

as such. What this meant for those who took their inspiration from<br />

Descartes was that man thereby replaced God. Trying to determine what<br />

was distinctive about the human will, Rousseau looked beneath the fi nite<br />

will to self-aggrandizement and found a general will that could never err,<br />

a will that Patrick Riley has shown is a direct descendent <strong>of</strong> God’s will that<br />

all men be saved. 31 Others saw this divine element not so much in man<br />

and his will but in the rationality <strong>of</strong> the natural world. Following Hobbes’<br />

identifi cation <strong>of</strong> mechanical causality and divine will, Spinoza developed<br />

a pantheistic account that identifi ed God and substance. Locke believed<br />

that one could fi nd moral imperatives suffi cient to guide human life within<br />

the divinely created natural world. 32 Newton saw time and space as the<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> divine being. Aft er these divine capacities had been transferred to<br />

man or nature, it was easy for the Encyclopedists Diderot, D’Alembert, and<br />

Holbach to demonstrate that revealed religion was not only false but also<br />

superfl uous. 33 By the end <strong>of</strong> the Enlightenment, many thinkers treated human<br />

beings as quasi-divine. Th is is especially clear in someone like Kant<br />

who asserts that human beings are infi nitely valuable ends in themselves. 34<br />

Such a view is only possible because <strong>of</strong> the transference <strong>of</strong> what hitherto<br />

were considered divine attributes to human beings. Th e Enlightenment<br />

(and post-Enlightenment) exaltation <strong>of</strong> human individuality is thus in<br />

fact a form <strong>of</strong> radical (although concealed) Pelagianism. Divine or at least<br />

quasi-divine powers reemerge although always in disguise. Nature is an<br />

embodied rational will; the social world is governed by an “invisible hand”<br />

that almost miraculously produces a rational distribution <strong>of</strong> goods and<br />

services; and history is the progressive development <strong>of</strong> humanity toward<br />

perfection.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!