19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

162 chapter five<br />

that schism was unavoidable. He had already recognized the likely result<br />

<strong>of</strong> Luther’s teaching in the Diatribe: “Th is seditious wantonness <strong>of</strong> your<br />

pen . . . brings destruction down on all good things.” 109 He had been convinced<br />

that Luther’s agitation would not eliminate corruption, improve<br />

morals, or foster real piety but instead would aggravate the “tyranny <strong>of</strong><br />

princes, bishops, theologians and monks”; liberal studies would be disregarded,<br />

and humanists regarded with deep suspicion. 110 Luther would thus<br />

shatter “the whole world with strife and destruction.” Nor was he willing to<br />

accept Luther’s assertion that this confl ict was inherent in the word, asserting<br />

that it was the result rather <strong>of</strong> how Luther had interpreted and preached<br />

the word. 111 All <strong>of</strong> these concerns aft er two years seemed to have been only<br />

too fully realized, and they scarcely needed to be pointed out in detail.<br />

Erasmus begins by defending his skepticism. He asserts that Luther has<br />

mischaracterized him as a skeptic who calls basic Christian doctrine into<br />

question when in fact he only suggests suspending judgment about obscure<br />

matters <strong>of</strong> interpretation on more peripheral issues. For Erasmus a<br />

skeptic is not someone who does not care what is true or false, but is rather<br />

someone who does not leap to conclusions or fi ght to the death for his<br />

own opinion. Luther, by contrast, acts as if he were God himself, asserting<br />

as certain what can at best be probable. Erasmus here again draws on<br />

the ancient debate and particularly on Carneades’ famous concept <strong>of</strong> the<br />

probable as a sensible alternative to Luther’s impossible, “Stoic” demand<br />

for certainty.<br />

Behind this discussion <strong>of</strong> the ways and extent to which we can understand<br />

Scripture lie radically diff erent and competing notions <strong>of</strong> what it<br />

means to be a human being and a Christian. For Erasmus humans are<br />

fallible and a Christian must constantly struggle along with others using<br />

every tool available to make sense out <strong>of</strong> revelation. God does not suddenly<br />

give us supernatural insight into the meaning <strong>of</strong> Scripture, and conversion<br />

is not a rapid and radical reversal but a gradual transformation. Here again<br />

Erasmus denies the Stoic core <strong>of</strong> Luther’s position. Th e knowledge that<br />

Luther and the Stoics claim to possess is merely an illusion. Even within<br />

the limited confi nes <strong>of</strong> the Stoic cosmos, such knowledge was scarcely conceivable.<br />

Th e Stoics themselves, for example, repeatedly wondered whether<br />

there had ever been a Stoic sage. For Christians the possibility <strong>of</strong> such<br />

knowledge is even more remote because the object <strong>of</strong> knowledge is not the<br />

fi nite cosmos but the infi nite God.<br />

Erasmus thus derides Luther’s claim to certain knowledge as hubristic<br />

and argues that such claims to divine knowledge put civilization at risk.<br />

He believes that Luther’s claim to divine inspiration is especially danger-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!