19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

petrarch and the invention <strong>of</strong> individuality 65<br />

quite critical <strong>of</strong> Epicurus but believes that there is much the two have in<br />

common. 152 Petrarch sees the summum bonum as honestas in contrast to<br />

Epicurus’s view that it is voluptas, but if virtue is always idiosyncratic to<br />

an individual’s own being, then it does not diff er from one doing whatever<br />

gives one pleasure, or to put it in other terms, honestas is indistinguishable<br />

in practice from voluptas. 153 Petrarch, <strong>of</strong> course, wants to deny<br />

such a conclusion, but it is clear that this possibility is present in Petrarch’s<br />

thought. 154 Whitfi eld quite plausibly suggests that modernity has subsequently<br />

never been wholly able to deny Epicurus his place. Whitfi eld admits<br />

that this turn to hedonism looks like a turn away from Petrarch, but<br />

he suggests it is rather a rejection <strong>of</strong> the negative elements in Petrarch’s<br />

thought in the context <strong>of</strong> a broader affi rmation <strong>of</strong> Petrarch’s essentially<br />

Epicurean position. 155<br />

In contradistinction to the charge that Petrarch betrays man’s humanity<br />

by denying his nature as the rational animal and the imago dei, critics<br />

have accused him <strong>of</strong> vastly exaggerating human potentialities by attributing<br />

a superhuman power to the human will. Petrarch’s notion <strong>of</strong> individuality<br />

seems particularly open to such a charge. He argues in the Remedies<br />

that God has demonstrated man’s superiority over all other creatures. 156<br />

Indeed, in refl ecting on Christ, he asserts that “so being made a man He<br />

might make man a god. . . . Does not this alone seem to ennoble somewhat<br />

the condition <strong>of</strong> man and to relieve a little <strong>of</strong> its misery? What more, pray,<br />

could man, I do not say hope for, but aim at, and think <strong>of</strong>, than to be God? .<br />

. . He did not assume any other body and soul than that <strong>of</strong> a man (although<br />

He could have done so).” 157 In this way Petrarch seems to magnify the capacities<br />

<strong>of</strong> the individual beyond human limits.<br />

While it is certainly the case that both <strong>of</strong> these charges can be plausibly<br />

leveled against Petrarch, I do not believe that either <strong>of</strong> them fi nally strikes<br />

to the core <strong>of</strong> his thought. Petrarch does not seek either to confi ne human<br />

being to the fi nite realm <strong>of</strong> mere matter in motion or to promote a striving<br />

to challenge God but pursues instead a middle course between Epicurus<br />

and Prometheus. He has a deep appreciation <strong>of</strong> the need for a sense <strong>of</strong> the<br />

infi nite (and eternal) in human life and is equally sure that man himself<br />

cannot supply or even ultimately comprehend it. Plotinus, according to<br />

Petrarch, recognized four kinds <strong>of</strong> virtue: political, purgatorial, purifi ed,<br />

and godly virtue. 158 Th e fi rst are the virtues <strong>of</strong> a Caesar or a Scipio. Th e second<br />

are the virtues <strong>of</strong> those private men who become followers <strong>of</strong> philosophy<br />

and successfully eradicate the passions that are only moderated in the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> the former. Petrarch puts himself in this group. Th e third are the<br />

virtues <strong>of</strong> the (Stoic) sage. As admirable as these may be, Petrarch doubts

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!