19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

300 notes to pages 22–26<br />

7. William <strong>of</strong> Ockham, Predestination, God’s Foreknowledge, and Future Contingents,<br />

ed. and trans. Marilyn McCord Adams and Norman Kretzmann, 2d ed.<br />

(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983), 13.<br />

8. Th e divine creation <strong>of</strong> a universal would thus entail a performative contradiction.<br />

Ockham I Sent. d. 2. q. 6.<br />

9. God can sustain any one thing in existence without the necessity <strong>of</strong> the existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> anything else in the universe. Funkenstein, Th eology, 135. See also André<br />

Goddu, Th e Physics <strong>of</strong> William <strong>of</strong> Ockham (Leiden and Cologne: Brill, 1984).<br />

10. On the ontological uniqueness <strong>of</strong> God as the nominalists understood him, see<br />

Martin Tweedale, “Scotus and Ockham on the Infi nity <strong>of</strong> the Most Eminent Being,”<br />

Franciscan Studies 23 (1963): 257–67.<br />

11. On this point, see Jean Largeault, Enquête sur le nominalisme (Paris and Louvain:<br />

Beatrice-Nauwelaerts, 1971), 154. God does not need universals since he can<br />

understand everything individually by means <strong>of</strong> his cognitio intuitiva. Adams,<br />

Ockham, 2:1036–56.<br />

12. II Sent. q. 14–15; q. 17; q. 18; q. 22; q. 24; IV Sent. q. 3; q. 8–9. Th e principle has<br />

several other forms. “No plurality should be assumed unless it can be proved by<br />

reason, or by experience, or by some infallible authority.” Ord. I, d. 30, qu. 1. Also:<br />

“One should affi rm no statement as true or maintain that something exists unless<br />

forced to do so by self-evidence, that is, by revelation, experience, or logical<br />

deduction from a revealed truth or a proposition verifi ed by observation.” I Sent.<br />

d. 30 q. 1; III Sent. q. 8.<br />

13. On the contingency <strong>of</strong> created things for Ockham, see I Sent. d. 35 q. 2; and II Sent.<br />

q. 4–5.<br />

14. Centiloquium theologicum conc. 6, 7a, ed. Philotheus Boehner (St. Bonaventure,<br />

N.Y.: St Bonaventure University Press, 1988), 44.<br />

15. Miethke, Ockhams Weg, 227, 275, 284; Blumenberg, Legitimacy, 164; Tweedale,<br />

“Scotus and Ockham,” 265.<br />

16. As severe as this position might seem, in one sense it ameliorates the Th omistic<br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> original sin since Ockham believes that no man intrinsically deserves<br />

damnation. On this point, see Adams, Ockham, 2:1257–1337.<br />

17. Ockham even asserts that God’s love <strong>of</strong> man is only a passage back to himself and<br />

thus an act <strong>of</strong> self-love. Blumenberg, Legitimacy, 174–77.<br />

18. On this point see David Clark, “Ockham on Human and Divine Freedom,” Franciscan<br />

Studies 38 (1978): 160.<br />

19. John Calvin, Institutes <strong>of</strong> the Christian Religion, ed., John McNeill, trans. Lewis<br />

Battles, 2 vols. (Philadelphia: Westminster, 1960), 1:162. On similar grounds, Hans<br />

Blumenberg has argued that we should understand nominalism as the second<br />

coming <strong>of</strong> Gnosticism. Legitimacy <strong>of</strong> the Modern Age, 127–36.<br />

20. Henning Graf Reventlow, Th e Authority <strong>of</strong> the Bible and the Rise <strong>of</strong> the Modern<br />

World (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1985), 35.<br />

21. Th ey wanted the pope, for example, to allow communal ownership <strong>of</strong> property.<br />

22. Th ey believed that God was not bound by his past acts and could predestine individuals<br />

as he wished. Adams, Ockham, 2:1201, 1257.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!