19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

336 notes to pages 187–193<br />

69. Lachterman, “Descartes and the Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History,” 38.<br />

70. AT 10:82; CSM 3:13. Th is is not to say that it is fi ctional but that it can only be proposed<br />

by means <strong>of</strong> a fi ction for it would otherwise be condemned and prohibited<br />

by the authorities.<br />

71. AT 4:486–92; CSM, 3:292–95.<br />

72. AT 6:23–24; CSM 1:122–23.<br />

73. G. W. F. Hegel, Sämmtliche Werke, ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl Markus Michel,<br />

20 vols. (Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 1970), 12:524.<br />

74. Descartes to Mersenne, May 6, 1630, May 27, 1638. AT 1:148, 2:138.<br />

75. For all <strong>of</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> theology, Descartes says almost nothing about salvation,<br />

damnation, or a life aft er death.<br />

76. Discourse, AT 6:61–63; CSM 1:142–43.<br />

77. AT 10:362; CSM 1:10–11.<br />

78. AT 10:359; CSM 1:9.<br />

79. AT 10:368; CSM 1:14.<br />

80. Even for Aristotle, deduction depends upon the knowledge <strong>of</strong> fi rst principles<br />

which are known by intuition (nous).<br />

81. AT 10:368–70; CSM 1:15.<br />

82. AT 10:421–27; CSM 1:46–49.<br />

83. AT 10:419–20; CSM 1:44–45.<br />

84. On the role <strong>of</strong> imagination in Descartes see Jacob Klein, Greek Mathematical<br />

Th ought and the <strong>Origins</strong> <strong>of</strong> Algebra, trans. Eva Brann (Cambridge: M.I.T. Press,<br />

1968), 197–211, 293–309; and Dennis Sepper, Descartes’ Imagination: Proportion,<br />

Image, and the Activity <strong>of</strong> Th inking (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University <strong>of</strong> California<br />

Press, 2004).<br />

85. Burman, AT 5:176–77. On this point see Stanley Rosen, “A Central Ambiguity in<br />

Descartes,” in Cartesian Essays: A Collection <strong>of</strong> Critical Studies, ed. Bernd Magnus<br />

and James B. Wilbur (Th e Hague: Nijh<strong>of</strong>f , 1969), 24.<br />

86. AT 10:420; CSM 1:45.<br />

87. Descartes rejects here a science that determines only what is likely. Such a science<br />

is not concerned with probability in the modern sense. Our notion <strong>of</strong> probability<br />

as it is understood within mathematical statistics helps us determine degrees <strong>of</strong><br />

doubtfulness or probability. Th is idea was unknown in Descartes’ time. On the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the modern notion <strong>of</strong> probability, see Ian Hacking, Th e Emergence<br />

<strong>of</strong> Probability (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975) and Lorraine<br />

Daston, Classical Probability in the Enlightenment (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton<br />

University Press, 1995).<br />

88. Dunn, “A Great City,” 100–101.<br />

89. Although the Meditations presents itself as the inner dialogue <strong>of</strong> an isolated man,<br />

it is really part <strong>of</strong> a dialogical interaction with some <strong>of</strong> the most noted thinkers <strong>of</strong><br />

the time. On the centrality <strong>of</strong> the Objections and Replies to Descartes’ thinking,<br />

see Jean-Luc Marion, “Th e Place <strong>of</strong> the Objections in the Development <strong>of</strong> Cartesian<br />

Metaphysics,” in Descartes and his Contemporaries: Meditations, Objections,<br />

and Replies, ed. Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago<br />

Press, 1995), 7–20.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!