19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

338 notes to pages 196–200<br />

intentional omnipotence by contrast may be less likely to produce error, but it is<br />

also impossible to remedy.<br />

103. AT 6:32; CSM 1:127.<br />

104. AT 7:25; CSM 2:17.<br />

105. AT 7:140–41; CSM 2:100. For the best alternative argument, see Heinrich Scholtz,<br />

“Über das Cogito, Ergo Sum,” Kant-Studien 36, no. 1/2 (1931):126–47.<br />

106. AT 6:33; 8A:8–9; CSM 1:127, 196.<br />

107. AT 7:25; CSM 2:16–17.<br />

108. On this point see Jaakko Hintikka, “Cogito, ergo sum: Inference or Performance?,”<br />

in Meta-Meditations, 50–76.<br />

109. AT 7:145–46; CSM 2:104; cf. Principles, AT 9B:9–10, CSM 1:183–84.<br />

110. AT 10:411; CSM 1:39.<br />

111. AT 7:28; CSM 2:19.<br />

112. AT 7:34; CSM 2:24.<br />

113. AT 7:160; CSM 2:133. See also Descartes to Mersenne, May 1637; and to Reneri,<br />

April-May 1638; AT 1:366; 2:36. Descartes gives a similar account plus memory in<br />

Th e Description <strong>of</strong> the Human Body, AT 11:224.<br />

114. AT B:17; CSM 1:204.<br />

115. AT 11:342–49; CSM 1:335–39. See also Descartes to Regius, May 1646; AT 3:372.<br />

116. Meditations, AT 7:27; CSM 2:18–19.<br />

117. Replies, AT 7:188–89; CSM 2:132.<br />

118. Comments on a Certain Broadsheet, AT 8B:363; CSM 1:307.<br />

119. On this point see Peter Schouls, Descartes and the Enlightenment (Edinburgh:<br />

Edinburgh University Press, 1989), esp. 35–50, and Antony Kenny, “Descartes on<br />

the Will,” in Cartesian Studies, ed. R. J. Butler (New York: Barnes and Noble,<br />

1972), 4. Descartes’ identifi cation <strong>of</strong> thinking as willing recalls the nominalist notion<br />

that for God knowing and creating are one and the same thing.<br />

120. AT 3:394; cf. Principles, AT 8A:7; CSM 1:195.<br />

121. On this point, see Gerhard Kruger, “Die Herrschaft des philosophischen Selbstbewusstseins,”<br />

Logos, Internationale Zeitschrift für Philosophie der Kultur 22<br />

(1933): 246.<br />

122. On this point, see Simon, “Les vérités éternelles de Descartes,” 126–29.<br />

123. See Heidegger, Nietzsche, 2 vols. (Pfullingen: Neske, 1961), 2:148–58.<br />

124. My interpretation thus is radically at odds with Sartre’s claim that Descartes attributes<br />

absolute freedom to God but not to man. Descartes (Paris: Trois collines,<br />

1946), 9–52.<br />

125. Meditations, AT 7:21–22; CSM 2:14–15.<br />

126. Th is conclusion is even more explicit in Descartes’ unfi nished dialogue, Th e Search<br />

for Truth, where Eudoxus calms the fears <strong>of</strong> Epistemon that the path <strong>of</strong> doubt leads<br />

to the skepticism <strong>of</strong> Socrates and the Pyrrhonists (AT 10:512; CSM 2:408) by demonstrating<br />

that because I doubt, that is, think, I am. AT 10:523; CSM 2:417. Th is is<br />

also highly reminiscent <strong>of</strong> the argument Augustine develops in the Confessions.<br />

127. “To be autarchic, one’s own commanding source, is both to be a principle oneself,<br />

that is, the generative or productive source <strong>of</strong> all that can be invented by sci-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!