19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

352 notes to pages 248–250<br />

141. Springborg, “Leviathan and the Problem <strong>of</strong> Ecclesiastical Authority,” 136. Hobbes’<br />

emphasis on reasonable interpretation favored broad access to Scripture. He<br />

criticized Puritans for using obscure language to ensnare people. White’s De<br />

Mundo, 478.<br />

142. See Ockham, I Sent. d. 2 q. 10, in Opera philosophica et theologica, ed. Stephen<br />

Brown (New York: Bonaventure Press, 1967), 355–56.<br />

143. On this point, see Martinich, Two Gods, 196.<br />

144. Damrosch, “Hobbes as Reformation Th eologian,” 345. Martinich notes the nominalist<br />

connection: since God is self-suffi cient, nothing humans can do benefi ts<br />

him. Two Gods, 128.<br />

145. Mintz, Hunting the Leviathan, 42. As Ronald Hepburn points out, discourse intended<br />

to honor God in Hobbes’ view is neither true nor false. “Hobbes on the<br />

Knowledge <strong>of</strong> God,” in Hobbes and Rousseau: A Collection <strong>of</strong> Critical Essays,<br />

ed. Maurice Cranston and Richard S. Peters (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday,<br />

1972), 99.<br />

146. Martinich points out that Hobbes’ insistence that God is corporeal has led some<br />

to think that he was a pantheist like Spinoza. Two Gods, 248. Hobbes does admit<br />

that Spinoza spoke more frankly than he did. See Edwin Curley, “‘I Durst<br />

Not Write So Boldly’ or, How to Read Hobbes’ Th eological-Political Treatise,” in<br />

Hobbes e Spinoza: Atti del Convegno Internazionale, Urbino 14–17 ottobre, 1988,<br />

ed. Daniela Bostrengi (Napels: Biblipolis, 1992): 497–593. However, Hobbes cannot<br />

be a pantheist because his God who acts and commands is not identical with<br />

the world. As Glover points out, Hobbes not only distinguished them but asserted<br />

that to identify them was to deny God’s existence. “God and Th omas Hobbes,”<br />

166. It is <strong>of</strong>t en asserted that while Hobbes himself may not have been an atheist,<br />

his teaching led to atheism. Th is argument, however, would seem to apply to most<br />

Reformation theologians.<br />

147. Such a claim would, <strong>of</strong> course, have left Hobbes open to the charge <strong>of</strong> occultism,<br />

which would itself certainly have led to his condemnation and probably to his<br />

death. Hobbes believed that the idea <strong>of</strong> an incorporeal God was not in Scripture<br />

but was due to the impact <strong>of</strong> Platonism on Christianity during the Patristic period.<br />

Such Platonism was anathema to Hobbes, who believed it was used by the<br />

church to undermine sovereignty.<br />

148. Hobbes probably does not explicitly develop this explanation because it would<br />

seem to vitiate his claim that we can only conceive <strong>of</strong> a cause as the action <strong>of</strong> one<br />

body on another. Th e deep problem that Hobbes leaves unexplained is how bodies<br />

can be both inaccessible to us and yet essential to our conceptualization <strong>of</strong> causality.<br />

Th is perplexity could be resolved by admitting that bodies are merely imaginary<br />

entities, that is, merely arbitrary signs for demarcating and understanding<br />

motion.<br />

149. Geach sees Hobbes as a Socinian, but this is unlikely. While Hobbes shared some<br />

<strong>of</strong> their beliefs, he did not share their ardent attachment to free will. “Th e Religion<br />

<strong>of</strong> Th omas Hobbes,” 285–87.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!