19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

notes to pages 201–205 339<br />

ence, and to be the principle <strong>of</strong> oneself, that is, to have one’s life and work under<br />

command. Later, in the Passions <strong>of</strong> the Soul, Descartes will give this autarchy the<br />

name ‘génerosité’—the key and coping-stone <strong>of</strong> all the other virtues.” Lachterman,<br />

“Descartes and the Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History,” 43.<br />

128. Replies, AT 7:144; CSM 2:103.<br />

129. Replies, AT 7:165; CSM 2:116–17.<br />

130. Replies, AT 7:106–7; CSM 2:77, 88. One might note that this is a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> perfection and not <strong>of</strong> God per se.<br />

131. Oedingen, “Der Genius Malignus,” 182; Harry G. Frankfurt, Demons, Dreamers,<br />

and Madmen: Th e Defense <strong>of</strong> Reason in Descartes’ Meditations (Indianapolis:<br />

Bobbs-Merrill, 1970), 172. Th us, according to Descartes, an atheist cannot attain<br />

certainty and cannot be a scientist. AT 7:139; CSM 2:99; cf. also Replies, AT 7:384;<br />

CSM 2:263.<br />

132. On this point I follow Marion’s argument in “Th e Essential Incoherence <strong>of</strong> Descartes’<br />

Conception <strong>of</strong> Divinity,” in Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, ed. Amélie<br />

Rorty (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1986), 297–338.<br />

133. Th at said, Anselm does not believe that God is therefore entirely incomprehensible.<br />

In fact, he argues that despite his inaccessibility God is the light that<br />

makes everything else comprehensible. Th e connection to the Platonic tradition<br />

is palpable.<br />

134. Where Descartes sees God sub specie infi nitatis, Bonaventure sees him sub specie<br />

divinitatis. Itinerarium mentis in Deum 3.4. See Koyré, Descartes und die<br />

Scholastik, 115–17.<br />

135. Jean Marie Beyssade, “Création des vérités éternelles et doubte metaphysique,”<br />

Studia Cartesiana 2 (1981): 93; and Marion, “Essential Incoherence,” 303–7.<br />

136. Descartes to Clersellier, 1646, AT 4:445–46; Descartes to Hyperaspistas, August<br />

1641, AT 3:427.<br />

137. Replies, AT 7:367–68; CSM 2:253.<br />

138. Replies, AT 7:371; CSM 2:256.<br />

139. Principles, AT 8A:15; CSM 1:202, Descartes to Chanut, June 6, 1647, AT 5:51. Margaret<br />

Wilson suggests the infi nite/indefi nite distinction may be a ploy since Descartes<br />

characterizes the human will as infi nite. Margaret Wilson, “Can I Be the<br />

Cause <strong>of</strong> My Idea <strong>of</strong> the World? (Descartes on the Infi nite and the Indefi nite),” in<br />

Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, 349–50.<br />

140. Replies, AT 7:112; CSM 2:81.<br />

141. Replies, AT 7:111–12, 365; CSM 2: 80, 252.<br />

142. Th e Cartesian understanding <strong>of</strong> the relation <strong>of</strong> God and nature is thus the culmination<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mystical identifi cation <strong>of</strong> the cosmos with the divine that began, as<br />

we saw in chapter 1, with Meister Eckhart.<br />

143. Or as S<strong>of</strong>f er puts it: “Cartesian nature has become de-theologized by means <strong>of</strong> a<br />

divine inscrutability as the personifi cation <strong>of</strong> Cartesian mechanics.” From Science<br />

to Subjectivity, 155.<br />

144. Th is reading <strong>of</strong> Descartes’ ontological argument pushes Descartes in the direction<br />

<strong>of</strong> Spinoza, who sees God as unthinking substance, Fichte, who sees God as an

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!