19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

150 chapter five<br />

For Erasmus it is crucial not that God be omnipotent but that he be<br />

good. 60 He thus tries to counterbalance Luther’s argument in order to<br />

preserve divine goodness and promote human responsibility. If humans<br />

did not have some degree <strong>of</strong> freedom, it is diffi cult to see how God could<br />

act justly in punishing sinners or what incentives humans could have to<br />

act morally. Erasmus was well aware that his position might be seen as Pelagian<br />

and tried to show why it was not. In his view there were fi ve diff erent<br />

competing positions on this issue. Pelagians believe that extraordinary<br />

works <strong>of</strong> charity or virtue can win salvation without grace. Scotists believe<br />

man is able to do morally good works without grace that merit salvation. 61<br />

Augustine believes that salvation requires grace alone but does not abolish<br />

the human will, which works in coordination with grace. Karlstadt<br />

believes that grace is essential and that the will is only free to do evil. And<br />

fi nally, Luther believes that grace is the source <strong>of</strong> everything and that the<br />

will is free to do neither good nor evil. Erasmus considers the positions <strong>of</strong><br />

Pelagius, Karlstadt and Luther to be unorthodox, that <strong>of</strong> Scotus acceptable<br />

but incorrect, and that <strong>of</strong> Augustine best and closest to his own.<br />

Erasmus believed that Christ’s sacrifi ce gave human beings the chance<br />

to accept or reject grace when God <strong>of</strong>f ered it to them. Th is sacrifi ce, however,<br />

did not entirely restore them to their prelapsarian state. In contrast to<br />

Adam before the Fall, the human will is now biased toward evil. 62 Humans<br />

consequently need God’s further assistance in completing the project that<br />

their free choice begins with its acceptance <strong>of</strong> grace. Erasmus thus asserts<br />

that while human beings owe the beginning and end <strong>of</strong> their redemption to<br />

God, the middle depends chiefl y on them. He consequently contends that<br />

his position is both Augustinian and orthodox. But is this the case?<br />

Th ere is some reason to doubt that Erasmus sincerely holds the view he<br />

describes here. Elsewhere he asserts that free will is “a power <strong>of</strong> the will,<br />

by means <strong>of</strong> which man is able to apply himself or turn away from the<br />

things that lead to eternal salvation.” 63 Th is statement seems to attribute<br />

much more to the will than the position outlined above. When discussing<br />

this matter, he also at times does not mention grace at all or suggests that<br />

nature itself is grace in the Neoplatonic manner we noted in Ficino. 64 Th is<br />

view is certainly problematic for most Christians, and it is hard to fi nd<br />

anyone other than Erasmus who defi nes man’s natural freedom in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> a supernatural goal without mentioning grace. 65 Th is point is further<br />

strengthened by the fact that Erasmus draws no distinction between natural<br />

and acquired freedom, which seems to imply that grace is not needed<br />

to help man regain his freedom. He thus seems to believe that the fallen<br />

will is not enslaved by sin. Given all this, it is diffi cult to see how Erasmus’s

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!