19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

194 chapter six<br />

are dubitable. Science is thus impossible, and Descartes is forced to wonder<br />

whether he himself is anything at all. As he puts it at the beginning <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Second Meditation, “I have convinced myself that there is absolutely nothing<br />

in the world, no sky, no earth, no minds, no bodies. Does it now follow<br />

that I too do not exist?”<br />

As rigorous and radical as this skepticism seems to be, many have<br />

doubted its sincerity. Th is question is bound up with the larger question<br />

<strong>of</strong> the sincerity <strong>of</strong> the Meditations and Descartes’ metaphysics as a whole.<br />

One group <strong>of</strong> interpreters, including Louis Laird, Charles Adam, Etienne<br />

Gilson, Lucien Laberthonnière, Jean Laport, Hiram Caton, Richard Kennington,<br />

and Stanley Rosen, believes that Descartes was above all else a<br />

scientist and that he turned to metaphysics only in order to make his science<br />

palatable to believers. From their point <strong>of</strong> view, his hyperbolic doubt<br />

is thoroughly insincere. 92 For them, Descartes never truly doubts the veracity<br />

<strong>of</strong> mathematics. A second group, which includes Alfred Espinas,<br />

Alexander Koyré, Henri Gouhier, and Jean-Luc Marion, sees Descartes<br />

sincerely troubled by skepticism but rejecting it in favor <strong>of</strong> a genuine religious<br />

life. For them the metaphysics <strong>of</strong> the Meditations is not merely a sop<br />

for believers but the pinnacle <strong>of</strong> Cartesian thought. Th ere is solid support<br />

for both views. Descartes, for example, clearly tries to shore up the metaphysical<br />

foundations <strong>of</strong> his science, something he believed Galileo, to his<br />

great detriment, had failed to do. 93<br />

While it is certainly true that this was one motive behind Descartes’<br />

hyperbolic skepticism, it is hard to believe that it is the only one, or that he<br />

was only attempting to defend himself against potential enemies among<br />

believers. In the fi rst instance we know that at least one <strong>of</strong> the reasons for<br />

writing the Meditations was to answer questions that had been posed to<br />

him by a variety <strong>of</strong> thinkers, at least some <strong>of</strong> whom (for example, Th omas<br />

Hobbes) could hardly be accused <strong>of</strong> excessive piety. Descartes’ concern<br />

with metaphysical and theological questions also clearly antedates the<br />

Meditations. For example, there are already metaphysical questions at play<br />

in the Little Notebook. Moreover, the challenge to the certainty <strong>of</strong> his science<br />

that so concerns him, as we noted above, does not require the actual<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> an omnipotent God but only his mere possibility. Descartes<br />

thus does not have to believe in such a God or even in any God at all to<br />

entertain such doubts. He only has to be unable to prove such a God’s nonexistence.<br />

In a certain sense then even if his metaphysics is constructed<br />

only to answer wild and hyperbolic doubts, those doubts are quite real and<br />

resolving them therefore quite important for Descartes’ enterprise. Unless<br />

Descartes can eliminate them, his science can never be apodictic. Th us,<br />

Descartes is not insincere when he writes to Mersenne on April 15, 1630: “I

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!