19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the contradictions <strong>of</strong> enlightenment 267<br />

Descartes by contrast, we reason not about words but about the objects<br />

that they signify, and mathesis universalis aims not merely at probable<br />

knowledge that gives us an eff ective mastery <strong>of</strong> nature at this time and<br />

place but at apodictic knowledge that can guarantee our mastery everywhere<br />

and always.<br />

If Hobbes is correct about the nature <strong>of</strong> reasoning, then as Descartes<br />

well knows, we can never be certain that our ideas correspond to the<br />

things themselves. For Descartes, the guarantee <strong>of</strong> such a correspondence<br />

is provided by God, but only if God is not a deceiver. Mathesis universalis<br />

thus depends on the demonstration <strong>of</strong> this fact, but such a demonstration<br />

itself depends on our being able to know God, on having an idea <strong>of</strong> God<br />

in us. Hobbes considers this impossible because God is infi nite, and all <strong>of</strong><br />

our ideas are drawn from the imagination <strong>of</strong> fi nite bodies. We can thus<br />

know <strong>of</strong> God’s existence only inferentially by the logical necessity <strong>of</strong> a fi rst<br />

cause.<br />

Here we see a great divide. For Descartes there is a pure thinking separate<br />

from the imagination. Our capacity for such pure thinking is in fact<br />

something that we share with God. Descartes explains in the fi ft h Reply<br />

that our true “ideas” are the same as those in the divine mind that has no<br />

corporeal imagination. Implicitly, Descartes thus argues here that man as<br />

res cogitans is divine or at least participates in some aspects <strong>of</strong> the divine.<br />

As we have seen, this is a point he makes explicitly in the body <strong>of</strong> the Meditations<br />

where he identifi es man’s infi nite will with the will <strong>of</strong> God. 21 For<br />

Hobbes, by contrast, we can have no idea <strong>of</strong> an incorporeal thing. Even<br />

things like emotions, which Descartes educes to support his point, are in<br />

Hobbes’ view nothing other than the thing that evokes the emotion plus its<br />

eff ect on our body. Hobbes thus concludes that since we have no idea <strong>of</strong> our<br />

self or <strong>of</strong> God except as body, Descartes’ whole argument collapses. Descartes<br />

argues, on the contrary, since we do have an idea <strong>of</strong> God, Hobbes’<br />

objection collapses. Argument at this point can go no further, since the<br />

parties fundamentally disagree about the nature <strong>of</strong> man, his capacities,<br />

and his relation to God.<br />

Hobbes bolsters his argument in the next four objections. He fi rst argues<br />

that there is no distinction between the imagination <strong>of</strong> things and<br />

the astronomical or mathematical idea <strong>of</strong> them. Both images or words and<br />

mathematical symbols are tools that we use to grasp and manipulate bodies.<br />

Mathematics thus does not give us access to a trans-corporeal reality<br />

as Descartes suggests. In a similar vein, Hobbes denies that there are different<br />

levels <strong>of</strong> being <strong>of</strong> the sort that Descartes employs to identify divine<br />

infi nity with perfection. Th ere is no sense in which some being has more

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!