19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

232 chapter seven<br />

any particular eff ect because <strong>of</strong> our lack <strong>of</strong> access to the things themselves.<br />

He like Bacon recognized that the same eff ect could be produced by a variety<br />

<strong>of</strong> causes, and he contented himself in the belief that while much God<br />

did might be above or beyond reason, he would never contradict it.<br />

Such a probabilistic position cannot serve as the basis for an apodictic<br />

science, because there can be no guarantee that the picture science paints<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world corresponds to reality. 84 Th e brilliance <strong>of</strong> Hobbes’ position is<br />

that this does not matter. It is not crucial that we know the actual causal<br />

chains that govern the motions <strong>of</strong> matter. For science to achieve its goal we<br />

need only hypothetical truth. Th e hypothetical picture that we construct<br />

need not correspond to the actual causal pathways by which events occur;<br />

it need only explain how to produce or prevent eff ects. Th e account<br />

that science gives <strong>of</strong> the world is thus only a construction, that is, a hypothesis.<br />

In a certain sense, however, hypothetical knowledge is superior<br />

to apodictic knowledge—apodictic knowledge is merely a description <strong>of</strong><br />

what God did do, according to his potentia ordinata, while hypothetical<br />

knowledge describes what God could have done by his potentia absoluta. 85<br />

Hypothetical reasoning in this case is an exercise not in mere analysis and<br />

description but in artifi ce itself. Th e hypothetical construction undertaken<br />

by science is thus akin to the actual construction by which God creates the<br />

natural world, and it can serve as the basis for the construction <strong>of</strong> one that<br />

is more conducive to human thriving. 86<br />

Th is new science that Hobbes develops rests upon an essentially nominalist<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> knowing that understands words as signs. Everything we<br />

know in his view we know through sensation. We are struck by external<br />

objects that impart a motion to our organs <strong>of</strong> sense, thus producing a motion<br />

in us, a phantasm. 87 Th e motions that continue in us Hobbes calls<br />

imagination. All knowledge, he argues, is either sensation or imagination.<br />

Our ability to think using these images, however, is limited because <strong>of</strong> our<br />

inability to hold them all together in our mind. Th is is due to the fact that<br />

each phantasm is unique. Th e solution to this problem and the foundation<br />

for science is the use <strong>of</strong> signs.<br />

Signs, Hobbes argues, are marks that serve to bring a particular thing before<br />

the mind. Th ey do not have to be words, as in the case <strong>of</strong> rocks that mark<br />

the end <strong>of</strong> a path, but the signs we most employ are words. Words name and<br />

link things. Words are either proper names, which point to specifi c things,<br />

or they are the names <strong>of</strong> names that link things together. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as words<br />

bring diff erent things together under a single term, they both assist and<br />

mislead the understanding. 88 Th e danger is that we forget the uniqueness <strong>of</strong><br />

the similar things and imagine some one universal thing <strong>of</strong> which they are

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!