19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

54 chapter two<br />

focus on Scipio and titled his poem Africa. In this work, Scipio’s triumph<br />

over Carthage and the virtues <strong>of</strong> republican Rome come in large measure<br />

to replace Caesar’s more problematic virtues and his foundation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Roman empire as the supreme model <strong>of</strong> the virtuous life. 55 In part this<br />

choice is a refl ection <strong>of</strong> Petrarch’s underlying republican sympathies,<br />

which were also evident in his friendship and support for Cola di Rienzo’s<br />

republican revolution in Rome in 1347. 56 Scipio, however, was also a better<br />

example for Petrarch because he was more refl ective and introspective<br />

than Caesar.<br />

Petrarch’s Scipio is beautiful, tall, barrel-chested, muscular, chaste, and<br />

tranquil; he possesses great gravity and grace; he is a harsh foe, a sweet<br />

friend, immune to fortune’s boons and blows, and indiff erent to wealth.<br />

He venerates true glory, is pious, fi lled with rectitude, confi dent in battle,<br />

and courageous. He is also a lover <strong>of</strong> solitude, beauty, justice, and his fatherland.<br />

57 It is hard to imagine a more perfect man. Scipio for Petrarch is<br />

exemplary not merely because he conquers Carthage but because he conquers<br />

himself. It is this that makes him a true paragon <strong>of</strong> virtue. 58 He not<br />

only is virtuous, virtue is the only thing that delights him. 59 Virtue, as he<br />

sees it, is the only truly lovable thing because it conquers death and insures<br />

one’s fame, which stands fast against everything except time that undoes<br />

everything. 60<br />

Petrarch’s Hannibal, by contrast, is a man without virtue. His martial<br />

skills are easily equal to those <strong>of</strong> Scipio, but he is faithless and untrustworthy,<br />

resentful <strong>of</strong> the world and the gods, cruel <strong>of</strong> heart, insatiate for<br />

blood, in league with infernal powers, given to savage wrath, impious, and<br />

overconfi dent. 61 All <strong>of</strong> his victories are thus hollow and empty because he<br />

is not master <strong>of</strong> himself but a slave to his passions. For similar reasons, he<br />

is incapable <strong>of</strong> true friendship and unable to endure solitude.<br />

Africa thus presents two supreme moral examples: the virtuous and heroic<br />

man who can disdain fortune because <strong>of</strong> the strength <strong>of</strong> his character,<br />

and the “Machiavellian” man who is willing to do anything to secure victory<br />

but who is never master <strong>of</strong> himself and his own desires. 62 Both dramatically<br />

and philosophically, however, the work is fl awed. Dramatically,<br />

its hero is simply too good. He combines all <strong>of</strong> the pagan social virtues and<br />

a kind <strong>of</strong> Christian otherworldliness. 63 He has nothing to overcome, no<br />

internal struggle, no fl aws with which we can sympathize. He is a statue<br />

placed on a pedestal so high above the reader’s head that it is scarcely possible<br />

to behold him, let alone emulate him.<br />

Philosophically, the work fails because it vacillates between the praise<br />

<strong>of</strong> fame and the praise <strong>of</strong> virtue. Petrarch knew that most great men are

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!