19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

66 chapter two<br />

that any such human beings ever existed. Finally, the virtues <strong>of</strong> the fourth<br />

category pertain to God alone and are utterly beyond human beings. Th e<br />

highest form <strong>of</strong> life possible for actual human beings, in Petrarch’s view,<br />

is thus the life <strong>of</strong> the man who truly masters his passions by eliminating<br />

rather than merely moderating them. For Petrarch such a life is only possible<br />

if it is led in private to please oneself and not in public for the praise<br />

<strong>of</strong> the multitude.<br />

Th e ability to succeed in such a life depends in good measure upon individual<br />

human capacities, and particularly the strength <strong>of</strong> one’s will, but<br />

Petrarch never claims that such capacities are all that is needed. Without<br />

Christ and his help, he asserts, no one can become wise and good. 159 Petrarch<br />

thus seems to reject Pelagianism. For Petrarch, God as the Trinity is<br />

the highest power, the highest wisdom, and the highest good. 160 Th is claim<br />

tells us a good deal about Petrarch’s theological views. Ancient thinkers<br />

such as Cicero, according to Petrarch, understood that the divine must<br />

be rational and good, but they did not and could not comprehend divine<br />

power because they were unable to grasp the divine capacity for creatio ex<br />

nihilo. Th is was the great breakthrough that Christ and Christianity made<br />

possible. 161 It is this crucial fact that “Epicurus and his followers could<br />

not know and our Aristotelian philosophers do not deign to know.” 162<br />

Th ey did not understand that the world is created through the word as<br />

an expression <strong>of</strong> divine will, that is, that the articulation <strong>of</strong> the word creates<br />

the world because it is the expression <strong>of</strong> divine will and power. Th e<br />

ancients were unable to understand such a God because they continued<br />

to measure all gods by human capacities. Omnipotence, however, is not<br />

possible for man. Like the nominalists Petrarch lays great emphasis on<br />

the omnipotence <strong>of</strong> the divine will and the radical separation <strong>of</strong> God<br />

and man.<br />

In contrast to the nominalists, however, Petrarch sees a God who is<br />

willful but not unsettling. For nominalism, the idea <strong>of</strong> absolute divine<br />

power had as its corollary divine unpredictability. For Petrarch, by contrast,<br />

God is “the one, the Good, the True, the stably abiding.” 163 As such,<br />

he is a lodestone for human beings: “Human longing is boundless and<br />

insatiable until it comes to rest in thee, above whom there is no place to<br />

which it could still rise.” 164 In his omnipotence, such a God, in Petrarch’s<br />

view, is both unreachable and yet infi nitely lovable. Petrarch ties together<br />

this view <strong>of</strong> the divine and the role <strong>of</strong> religion in human life with his concern<br />

for virtue in his late treatise, “Of Our Own Ignorance and Th at <strong>of</strong> Many<br />

Others”:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!