19.01.2013 Views

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

Theological Origins of Modernity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

328 notes to pages 148–152<br />

50. Erasmus, Collected Works, 76:199.<br />

51. Ibid., 76:210.<br />

52. Ibid., 76:218.<br />

53. Ibid., 76:252.<br />

54. Ibid., 76:245, 261.<br />

55. Ibid., 76:190.<br />

56. Ibid., 76:286, 77:349.<br />

57. Ibid., 76:289.<br />

58. Cornelis Augustijn, Erasmus: His Life, Works, Infl uence, trans. J. C. Grayson (Toronto:<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Toronto Press, 1991), 139.<br />

59. Charles Trinkaus, “Erasmus, Augustine, and the Nominalists,” Archiv für Reformationsgeschichte<br />

67 (1976): 9. Erasmus was especially concerned by Luther’s<br />

radical claim that man remains a sinner even aft er he is justifi ed by grace (8).<br />

60. Rabil, “Desiderius Erasmus,” 254.<br />

61. Th e view <strong>of</strong> freedom that Erasmus assigns to Scotus is more properly assigned<br />

to Biel. Gordon Rupp, trans. and ed., Luther and Erasmus: Free Will and Salvation<br />

(Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1969), 11. In contrast to Luther, Erasmus<br />

sees nothing unacceptable in Biel’s position. McSorley, Luther: Right or Wrong,<br />

290–91.<br />

62. Gerrish, “De Libero Arbitrio (1524),” 196.<br />

63. Tracy, “Two Erasmuses, Two Luthers,” 72.<br />

64. Ibid., 208.<br />

65. McSorley, Luther: Right or Wrong, 285.<br />

66. Oberman, Luther, 216. Luther was convinced that little time was left . Köselleck<br />

notes that he became extremely angry when Melanchthon suggested that the<br />

Apocalypse might not occur for another four hundred years. Cited in Reinhardt<br />

Köselleck, “Historia Magistra Vitae. Über die Aufl ösung des Topos im horizont<br />

neuzeitlich bewegter Geschichte,” in Natur und Geschichte: Karl Löwith zu 70.<br />

Geburtstag, ed. G. Braun and M. Riedel (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1967), 212.<br />

67. Surprisingly, Luther never seizes on Erasmus’s truly Pelagian notion that nature is<br />

itself divine grace. Tracy, “Two Erasmuses, Two Luthers,” 43.<br />

68. Boyle, Rhetoric and Reform, 60.<br />

69. Oberman, Luther, 301; Tracy, “Two Erasmuses, Two Luthers,” 44.<br />

70. WA 18:600–601.29; LW 33:15–17.<br />

71. Boyle, Rhetoric and Reform, 46.<br />

72. WA 18:603.22–23; LW 33:20.<br />

73. Boyle, Rhetoric and Reform, 47–48. Bernard Wills defi nes this notion: “A kataleptic<br />

impression was defi ned as one . . . stamped and molded out <strong>of</strong> the object<br />

from which it came with a character such as it could not have if it came from an<br />

object other than the one which it did come from (Cicero, Academica 2.18). . . . If<br />

a certain impression had the character <strong>of</strong> a kataleptic impression, it could compel<br />

assent to the objective reality <strong>of</strong> that which was conveyed in the impression. . . . On<br />

this basis all forms <strong>of</strong> conceptual knowledge were thought to rest. Secure in his<br />

grasp <strong>of</strong> the physical Cosmos the Stoic was secure as well in his grasp <strong>of</strong> the divine

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!