25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

130<br />

some structural components of a theory of experience<br />

to do with degrees of falsifiability. But if the statements at issue<br />

are formulated as empirical hypotheses, then we find that the two<br />

concepts, simplicity and falsifiability, coincide in this case also.<br />

Let us consider what experiments may help us to test the hypothesis,<br />

‘In our world, we have to employ a certain metrical geometry with<br />

such and such a radius of curvature.’ A test will be possible only if we<br />

identify certain geometrical entities with certain physical objects—for<br />

instance straight lines with light rays; or points with the intersection of<br />

threads. If such an identification (a correlating definition, or perhaps an<br />

ostensive definition; cf. section 17) is adopted, then it can be shown<br />

that the hypothesis of the validity of an Euclidean light-ray-geometry is<br />

falsifiable to a higher degree than any of the competing hypotheses<br />

which assert the validity of some non-Euclidean geometry. For if we<br />

measure the sum of the angles of a light-ray triangle, then any significant<br />

deviation from 180 degrees will falsify the Euclidean hypothesis.<br />

The hypothesis of a Bolyai-Lobatschewski geometry with given curvature,<br />

on the other hand, would be compatible with any particular<br />

measurement not exceeding 180 degrees. Moreover, to falsify this<br />

hypothesis it would be necessary to measure not only the sum of the<br />

angles, but also the (absolute) size of the triangle; and this means that<br />

in addition to angles, a further unit of measurement, such as a unit of<br />

area, would have to be defined. Thus we see that more measurements<br />

are needed for a falsification; that the hypothesis is compatible with<br />

greater variations in the results of measurements; and that it is therefore<br />

more difficult to falsify: it is falsifiable to a lesser degree. To put it<br />

in another way, Euclidean geometry is the only metric geometry with a<br />

definite curvature in which similarity transformations are possible. In<br />

consequence, Euclidean geometrical figures can be invariant with<br />

respect to more transformations; that is, they can be of lower<br />

dimension: they can be simpler.<br />

46 CONVENTIONALISM AND THE<br />

CONCEPT OF SIMPLICITY<br />

What the conventionalist calls ‘simplicity’ does not correspond to what<br />

I call ‘simplicity’. It is the central idea of the conventionalist, and also<br />

his starting point, that no theory is unambiguously determined by

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!