25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

54 FINITE SEQUENCES. ORDINAL SELECTION AND<br />

NEIGHBOURHOOD SELECTION<br />

probability 147<br />

Let us suppose that the elements of a finite reference-class α are numbered<br />

(for instance that a number is written on each button in the box), and<br />

that they are arranged in a sequence, in accordance with these ordinal<br />

numbers. In such a sequence we can distinguish two kinds of selection<br />

which have special importance, namely selection according to the<br />

ordinal number of an element, or briefly, ordinal selection, and<br />

selection according to its neighbourhood.<br />

Ordinal selection consists in making a selection, from the sequence α, in<br />

accordance with a property β which depends upon the ordinal number<br />

of the element (whose selection is to be decided on). For example β<br />

may be the property even, so that we select from α all those elements<br />

whose ordinal number is even. The elements thus selected form a<br />

selected sub-sequence. Should a property γ be independent of an ordinal<br />

selection according to β, then we can also say that the ordinal selection is<br />

independent with respect to γ; or we can say that the sequence α is,<br />

with respect to γ, insensitive to a selection of β-elements.<br />

Neighbourhood selection is made possible by the fact that, in ordering the<br />

elements in a numbered sequence, certain neighbourhood relations are<br />

created. This allows us, for example, to select all those members whose<br />

immediate predecessor has the property γ; or, say, those whose first<br />

and second predecessors, or whose second successor, have the property<br />

γ; and so on.<br />

Thus if we have a sequence of events—say tosses of a coin—we have<br />

to distinguish two kinds of properties: its primary properties such as<br />

‘heads’ or ‘tails’, which belong to each element independently of its<br />

position in the sequence; and its secondary properties such as ‘even’ or<br />

‘successor of tails’, etc., which an element acquires by virtue of its<br />

position in the sequence.<br />

A sequence with two primary properties has been called ‘alternative’.<br />

As von Mises has shown, it is possible to develop (if we are<br />

careful) the essentials of the theory of probability as a theory of alternatives,<br />

without sacrificing generality. Denoting the two primary properties<br />

of an alternative by the figures ‘1’ and ‘0’, every alternative can be<br />

represented as a sequence of ones and zeros.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!