25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

364<br />

new appendices<br />

In order to prove now that, in any consistent interpretation, S must<br />

be a Boolean algebra, we note that<br />

(98) ((x)p(a, x) = p(b, x)) → p(ay, z) = p(by, z) B2<br />

(99) ((x)p(a, x) = p(b, x)) → p(y, az) = p(y, bz) 98, A2<br />

It is interesting that (99) needs A2: it does not follow from 98, 40, and<br />

B2, since it is possible that p(a, z) = p(b, z) = 0. (This will be the case, for<br />

example, if ā = z ≠ xx¯.)<br />

(100) ((x)(p(a, x) = p(b, x) & p(c, x) = p(d, x))) → p(ac, y) = p(bd, y)<br />

99, B2<br />

With the help of (90), of (100), and of A2, it can now easily be<br />

shown at once that whenever the condition<br />

(*)<br />

p(a, x) = p(b, x) for every x in S<br />

is satisfied, any name of the element a may be substituted for some or<br />

all occurrences of names of the element b in any well-formed formula<br />

of the calculus without changing its truth value; or in other words, the<br />

condition (*) guarantees the substitutional equivalence of a and b.<br />

In view of this result, we now define the Boolean equivalence of two<br />

elements, a and b, as follows.<br />

(D1) a = b ↔ (x)p(a, x) = p(b, x)<br />

From this definition we obtain at once the formulae<br />

(A) a = a<br />

(B) a = b → b = a<br />

(C) (a = b & b = c) → a = c<br />

(D) a = b → a may replace b in some or all places of any formula<br />

without affecting its truth value. A2, 90, 100<br />

We may also introduce a second definition<br />

(D2) a = b + c ↔ a = b c¯

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!