25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

360<br />

new appendices<br />

(Applying B2 twice to each side of (62) only leads to a conditional<br />

form with ‘p(bc, d)≠0 → ’ as antecedent.)<br />

I now turn to a generalization of the axiom of complementation, C. I<br />

shall be a little more concise in my derivations from now on.<br />

(63) p(b¯, b) ≠ 0 ↔ (c)p(c, b) = 1 7, 25<br />

(64) p(a, b) + p(ā, b) = 1 + p(b¯, b) C, 25, 63<br />

This is an unconditional form of the principle of complementation,<br />

C, which I am now going to generalize.<br />

In view of the fact that (64) is unconditional, and that ‘a’ does not<br />

occur on the right-hand side, we can substitute ‘c’ for ‘a’ and assert<br />

(65) p(a, b) + p(ā, b) = p(c, b) + p(c¯, b) 64<br />

(66) p(a, bd) + p(ā, bd) = p(c, bd) + p(c¯, bd) 65<br />

By multiplying with p(b, d) we get:<br />

(67) p(ab, d) + p(āb, d) = p(cb, d) + p(c¯b, d) B2, 66<br />

This is a generalization of (65). By substitution, we get:<br />

(68) p(ab, c) + p(āb, c) = p(cb, c) + p(c¯b, c). 67<br />

In view of<br />

(69) p(c¯b, c) = p(c¯, c), 7, B1, 25, 63<br />

we may also write (68) more briefly, and in analogy to (64),<br />

(70) p(ab, c) + p(āb, c) = p(b, c) + p(c¯, c). 68, 69 1<br />

1 In the derivation of (70) we also need the following formula<br />

p(cb, c) = p(b, c),<br />

which may be called ‘(29′)’. Its derivation, in the presence of (40) and (32) is analogous<br />

to the steps (28) and (29):

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!