25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

appendix *ix 411<br />

corroboration or acceptability cannot be a probability as one of the more<br />

interesting findings of the philosophy of knowledge. It can be put very<br />

simply like this. A report of the result of testing a theory can be<br />

summed up by an appraisal. This can take the form of assigning some<br />

degree of corroboration to the theory. But it can never take the form<br />

of assigning to it a degree of probability; for the probability of a statement<br />

(given some test statements) simply does not express an appraisal of the severity of the<br />

tests a theory has passed, or of the manner in which it has passed these tests. The main<br />

reason for this is that the content of a theory—which is the same as its<br />

improbability—determines its testability and its corroborability.<br />

I believe that these two ideas—content and degree of corroboration—are the<br />

most important <strong>logic</strong>al tools developed in my book. 8<br />

So much by way of introduction. In the three notes which follow<br />

here I have left the word ‘confirmation’ even where I should now only<br />

write ‘corroboration’. I have also left ‘P(x)’ where I now usually write<br />

‘p(x)’. But I have corrected some misprints; 9 and I have added a few<br />

footnotes, preceded by stars, and also two new points, *13 and *14, to<br />

the end of the Third Note.<br />

8<br />

As far as I am aware, the recognition of the significance of the empirical content or assertive<br />

power of a theory; the suggestion that this content increases with the class of the potential<br />

falsifiers of the theory—that is to say, the states of affairs which it forbids, or excludes<br />

(see sections 23, and 31); and the idea that content may be measured by the improbability<br />

of the theory, were not taken by me from any other source but were ‘all my own<br />

work’. I was therefore surprised when I read in Carnap’s Introduction to Semantics, 1942, p.<br />

151, in connection with his definition of ‘content’: ‘. . . the assertive power of a sentence<br />

consists in its excluding certain states of affairs (Wittgenstein); the more it excludes, the<br />

more it asserts.’ I wrote to Carnap, asking for details and reminding him of certain<br />

relevant passages in my book. In his reply he said that his reference to Wittgenstein was<br />

due to an error of memory, and that he actually had a passage from my book in mind;<br />

and he repeated this correction in his Logical Foundations of Probability, 1950, p. 406. I<br />

mention this here because in a number of papers published since 1942, the idea of<br />

content—in the sense of empirical or informative content—has been attributed, without<br />

definite reference, to Wittgenstein, or to Carnap, and sometimes to Wittgenstein and<br />

myself. But I should not like anybody to think that I have taken it without acknowledgement<br />

from Wittgenstein or anybody else: as a student of the history of ideas, I think that<br />

it is quite important to refer to one’s sources. (See also my discussion in section 35 of<br />

the distinction between <strong>logic</strong>al content and empirical content, with references to Carnap in<br />

footnotes 1 and 2.)<br />

9 I have also, of course, incorporated the corrections mentioned in B.J.P.S. 5, pp. 334<br />

and 359.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!