25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

probability 199<br />

events are, or are not, determined in themselves, I shall not examine it<br />

further here. (Cf. section 71 and 78.) If we are successful with our<br />

prediction, we may speak of ‘laws’; otherwise we can know nothing<br />

about the existence or non-existence of laws or of irregularities.* 2<br />

Perhaps more worth considering than this metaphysical idea is the<br />

following view. We encounter ‘chance’ in the objective sense, it may be<br />

said, when our probability estimates are corroborated; just as we<br />

encounter causal regularities when our predictions deduced from laws<br />

are corroborated.<br />

The definition of chance implicit in this view may not be altogether<br />

useless, but it should be strongly emphasized that the concept so<br />

defined is not opposed to the concept of law: it was for this reason that<br />

I called probability sequences chance-like. In general, a sequence of<br />

experimental results will be chance-like if the frame conditions which<br />

define the sequence differ from the initial conditions; when the individual<br />

experiments, carried out under identical frame conditions, will<br />

proceed under different initial conditions, and so yield different<br />

results. Whether there are chance-like sequences whose elements are in<br />

no way predictable, I do not know. From the fact that a sequence is<br />

chance-like we may not even infer that its elements are not predictable,<br />

or that they are ‘due to chance’ in the subjective sense of insufficient<br />

knowledge; and least of all may we infer from this fact the ‘objective’<br />

fact that there are no laws.* 3<br />

* 2 In this paragraph, I dismissed (because of its metaphysical character) a metaphysical<br />

theory which I am now, in my Postscript, anxious to recommend because it seems to me to<br />

open new vistas, to suggest the resolution of serious difficulties, and to be, perhaps, true.<br />

Although when writing this book I was aware of holding metaphysical beliefs, and<br />

although I even pointed out the suggestive value of metaphysical ideas for science, I was<br />

not alive to the fact that some metaphysical doctrines were rationally arguable and, in<br />

spite of being irrefutable, criticizable. See especially the last section of my Postscript.<br />

* 3 It would have been clearer, I think, had I argued as follows. We can never repeat an<br />

experiment precisely—all we can do is to keep certain conditions constant, within certain<br />

limits. It is therefore no argument for objective fortuity, or chance, or absence of law, if<br />

certain aspects of our results repeat themselves, while others vary irregularly; especially if<br />

the conditions of the experiment (as in the case of spinning a penny) are designed with a<br />

view to making conditions vary. So far, I still agree with what I have said. But there may<br />

be other arguments for objective fortuity; and one of these, due to Alfred Landé (‘Landé’s<br />

blade’) is highly relevant in this context. It is now discussed at length in my Postscript,<br />

sections *90, f.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!