25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

280<br />

some structural components of a theory of experience<br />

The advance of science is not due to the fact that more and more<br />

perceptual experiences accumulate in the course of time. Nor is it due<br />

to the fact that we are making ever better use of our senses. Out of<br />

uninterpreted sense-experiences science cannot be distilled, no matter<br />

how industriously we gather and sort them. Bold ideas, unjustified<br />

anticipations, and speculative thought, are our only means for interpreting<br />

nature: our only organon, our only instrument, for grasping<br />

her. And we must hazard them to win our prize. Those among us who<br />

are unwilling to expose their ideas to the hazard of refutation do not<br />

take part in the <strong>scientific</strong> game.<br />

Even the careful and sober testing of our ideas by experience is in its<br />

turn inspired by ideas: experiment is planned action in which every<br />

step is guided by theory. We do not stumble upon our experiences, nor<br />

do we let them flow over us like a stream. Rather, we have to be active:<br />

we have to ‘make’ our experiences. It is we who always formulate the<br />

questions to be put to nature; it is we who try again and again to put<br />

these question so as to elicit a clear-cut ‘yes’ or ‘no’ (for nature does<br />

not give an answer unless pressed for it). And in the end, it is again we<br />

who give the answer; it is we ourselves who, after severe scrutiny,<br />

decide upon the answer to the question which we put to nature—after<br />

protracted and earnest attempts to elicit from her an unequivocal ‘no’.<br />

‘Once and for all’, says Weyl, 4 with whom I fully agree, ‘I wish to<br />

record my unbounded admiration for the work of the experimenter in<br />

his struggle to wrest interpretable facts from an unyielding Nature who<br />

knows so well how to meet our theories with a decisive No—or with an<br />

inaudible Yes.’<br />

The old <strong>scientific</strong> ideal of epistēmē—of absolutely certain, demonstrable<br />

knowledge—has proved to be an idol. The demand for <strong>scientific</strong><br />

objectivity makes it inevitable that every <strong>scientific</strong> statement must<br />

remain tentative for ever. It may indeed be corroborated, but every corroboration<br />

is relative to other statements which, again, are tentative.<br />

Only in our subjective experiences of conviction, in our subjective<br />

faith, can we be ‘absolutely certain’. 5<br />

4 Weyl, Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik, 1931, p. 2. English translation by H. P. Robertson:<br />

The Theory of Groups and Quantum Mechanics, 1931, p. xx.<br />

5 Cf. for example note 3 to section 30. This last remark is of course a psycho<strong>logic</strong>al<br />

remark rather than an epistemo<strong>logic</strong>al one; cf. sections 7 and 8.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!