25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

appendix iv 295<br />

αF′(1) = αF′(0) = 1 2.<br />

By using the procedure employed in the proof of the third form of<br />

the binomial formula (section 60) or of the theorem of Bernoulli<br />

(section 61), it can be shown (with any degree of approximation) for<br />

whatever frequency value we may choose that there exist sequences which are<br />

‘absolutely free’—provided only that we make the assumption (which<br />

we have just proved) that at least one sequence exists which is absolutely<br />

free.<br />

with n1 = 4. We next construct the n1 − 1-free (i.e. 3-free) period determined by the<br />

method of note *1. It is<br />

1 1 1 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 1 1 0 1 0<br />

We re-arrange this so that it begins with our commencing sequence (1), which yields<br />

(2)<br />

0 1 1 0 1 0 1 1 1 1 0 0 0 0 1 0<br />

Since n2 = 16, we have next to construct, by the method of note *1, a 15-free period<br />

(3) of the length 2 16 = 65,536. Once we have constructed this 15-free period (3), we<br />

must be able to discover where, in this long period, our sequence (2) occurs. We then<br />

re-arrange (3) so that it commences with (2), and proceed to construct (4), of the<br />

length 2 65,536 .<br />

A sequence constructed in this way may be called a ‘shortest random-like sequence’ (i)<br />

because every step of its construction consists in the construction, for some n, of a<br />

shortest n-free period (cf. note *1 above), and (ii) because the sequence is so constructed<br />

that, whatever the stage of its construction, it always begins with a shortest n-free period.<br />

As a consequence, this method of construction ensures that every beginning piece of the<br />

length<br />

is a shortest n-free period for the largest possible n (i.e. for n = (log 2m) − 1).<br />

This property of ‘shortness’ is very important; for we can always obtain n-free, or<br />

absolutely free, sequences with equidistribution which commence with a finite segment<br />

of any chosen length m such that this finite segment has no random character but consists<br />

of say, only zeros, or only ones, or of any other intuitively ‘regular’ arrangement; which<br />

shows that for applications, the demand for n-freedom, or even absolute freedom, is not<br />

enough, and must be replaced by something like a demand for n-freedom, becoming<br />

manifest from the beginning; which is, precisely, what a ‘shortest’ random-like sequence<br />

achieves, in the most radical fashion possible. Thus they alone can set an ideal standard<br />

for randomness. For these ‘shortest’ sequences, convergence can be proved immediately, as<br />

opposed to the examples under (b) and (c) below. See also appendix *vi.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!