25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

the same likelihood—i.e.P(e, h) = 0.9930—as would statistical evidence e′,<br />

based on only a hundred tosses and δ = 0.135.* 5 (But it is quite<br />

satisfactory to find that E(h, e) = 0.9946 while E(h, e′) = 0.7606.)<br />

11. It should be noticed that the absolute <strong>logic</strong>al probability of a<br />

universal law h—that is, P(h)—will be in general zero, in an infinite<br />

universe. For this reason, P(e, h)—that is, the likelihood of h—will<br />

become indefinite, in most systems of probability, since in most systems<br />

P(e, h) is defined as P(eh)/P(h) = 0/0. We therefore need a formal<br />

calculus of probability which yields definite values for P(e, h) even if<br />

P(h) = 0, and which will always and unambiguously yield P(e, h) = 1<br />

whenever e follows (or ‘almost follows’) from h. A system answering<br />

these demands was published by me some time ago. 7<br />

12. Our E(h, e) may be adequately interpreted as a measure of the<br />

explanatory power of h with respect to e, even if e is not a report<br />

of genuine and sincere attempts to refute h. But our C(h, e) can be<br />

adequately interpreted as degree of corroboration of h—or of the<br />

rationality of our belief in h, in the light of tests—only if e consists of<br />

reports of the outcome of sincere attempts to refute h, rather than of<br />

attempts to verify h.<br />

As hinted in the preceding sentence, I suggest that, while it is a<br />

mistake to think that probability may be interpreted as a measure of the<br />

rationality of our beliefs (this interpretation is excluded by the paradox<br />

of perfect evidence), degree of corroboration may be so interpreted. 8<br />

As to the calculus of probability, it has a very large number of different<br />

interpretations. 9 Although ‘degree of rational belief’ is not among<br />

* 5 Fisher’s ‘likelihood’ turns out to be in many cases intuitively unsatisfactory. Let x be<br />

‘the next throw with this die is a six’. Then the likelihood of x in the light of the evidence<br />

y will be 1, and thus at its maximal value, if we take y to mean, for example, ‘the next<br />

throw is even’, or ‘the next throw is a number > 4’ or even ‘the next throw is a number<br />

other than 2’. (The values of C(x, y) are satisfactory, it seems: they are, respectively, 3/8;<br />

4/7; and 1/10.)<br />

7 This Journal, 1955, 6; see esp. 56 sq. A simplified form of this axiom system may be<br />

found in my papers ‘Philosophy of Science: A Personal Report’ (p. 191) and ‘The Propensity<br />

Interpretation’, etc., referred to in note 3 above. (In the latter paper, p. 67, note 3,<br />

the last occurrence of ‘ < ’ should be replaced by ‘≠’, and in (B) and (C) a new line<br />

should commence after the second arrows.) *See the new appendices *iv and *v.<br />

8 Cf. this Journal, 1955, 6, 55 (the title of the section).<br />

9 Cf. my note in Mind, 1938, 47, 275 sq.<br />

appendix *ix 433

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!