25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

some observations on quantum theory 231<br />

this section to an imaginary experiment proposed by Einstein 7 and<br />

called by Jeans 8 ‘one of the most difficult parts of the new quantum<br />

theory’; though I think that our interpretation makes it perfectly clear,<br />

if not trivial.* 4<br />

Imagine a semi-translucent mirror, i.e. a mirror which reflects part of<br />

the light, and lets part of it through. The formally singular probability<br />

that one given photon (or light quantum) passes through the mirror,<br />

αP k(β), may be taken to be equal to the probability that it will be<br />

reflected; we therefore have<br />

αP k(β) = αP k(β - ) = 1 2.<br />

This probability estimate, as we know, is defined by objective statistical<br />

probabilities; that is to say, it is equivalent to the hypothesis that one<br />

half of a given class α of light quanta will pass through the mirror<br />

whilst the other half will be reflected. Now let a photon k fall upon the<br />

mirror; and let it next be experimentally ascertained that this photon<br />

has been reflected: then the probabilities seem to change suddenly, as it<br />

were, and discontinuously. It is as though before the experiment they<br />

had both been equal to 1 2, while after the fact of the reflection became<br />

known, they had suddenly turned into 0 and to 1, respectively. It is<br />

plain that this example is really the same as that given in section 71.* 5<br />

And it hardly helps to clarify the situation if this experiment is<br />

described, as by Heisenberg, 9 in such terms as the following: ‘By the<br />

experiment [i.e. the measurement by which we find the reflected<br />

7 Cf. Heisenberg, Physikalische Prinzipien, p. 29 (English translation by C. Eckart and<br />

F. C. Hoyt: The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory, Chicago, 1930, p. 39).<br />

8 Jeans, The New Background of Science (1933, p. 242; 2nd edition, p. 246).<br />

* 4 The problem following here has since become famous under the name ‘The problem<br />

of the (discontinuous) reduction of the wave packet’. Some leading physicists told me in 1934<br />

that they agreed with my trivial solution, yet the problem still plays a most bewildering<br />

role in the discussion of the quantum theory, after more than twenty years. I have<br />

discussed it again at length in sections *100 and *115 of the Postscript.<br />

* 5 That is to say, the probabilities ‘change’ only in so far as α is replaced by β - . Thus αP(β)<br />

remains unchanged 1 2; but β -P(β), of course, equals 0, just as β -P(β - ) equals 1.<br />

9 Heisenberg, Physikalische Prinzipien, p. 29 (English translation: The Physical Principles of<br />

the Quantum Theory, Chicago, 1930, p. 39). Von Laue, on the other hand, in Korpuskularund<br />

Wellentheorie, Handbuch d. Radiologie 6 (2nd edition, p. 79 of the offprint) says quite<br />

rightly: ‘But perhaps it is altogether quite mistaken to correlate a wave with one single

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!