25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

some observations on quantum theory 241<br />

there must correspond a second particle, of [B], which was deflected at<br />

P with the momentum b 2, in the calculable direction PY. We now place<br />

an apparatus at X—for instance a Geiger-counter or a moving film<br />

strip—which records the impacts of particles arriving from P at the<br />

arbitrarily restricted region X. Then we can say: as we note any such<br />

recording of a particle, we learn at the same time that a second particle<br />

must be travelling from P with the momentum b 2 towards Y. And we<br />

also learn from the recording where this second particle was at any<br />

given moment; for we can calculate from the time of the impact of the<br />

first particle at X, and from its known velocity, the moment of its<br />

collision at P. By using another Geiger-counter at Y (or the moving film<br />

band), we can test our predictions for the second particle.* 4<br />

The precision of these predictions as well as that of the measurements<br />

undertaken to test them is in principle not subject to any of the limitations<br />

due to the uncertainty principle, as regards both the position co-ordinate and<br />

the component of the momentum in the direction PY. For my imaginary<br />

experiment reduces the question of the precision with which predictions<br />

can be made about a B-particle deflected in P to the question of<br />

the precision attainable in taking measurements at X. These, at first,<br />

seemed to be non-predictive measurements of the time, position and<br />

momentum of the corresponding first particle [A]. The momentum of<br />

this particle in the PX direction as well as the time of its impact at X, i.e.<br />

of its position in the PS direction, can be measured with any desirable<br />

degree of precision (cf. appendix vi) if we make a momentum selection<br />

* 4 Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen use a weaker but valid argument: let Heisenberg’s interpretation<br />

be correct, so that we can only measure at will either the position or the<br />

momentum of the first particle at X. Then if we measure the position of the first particle, we<br />

can calculate the position of the second particle; and if we measure the momentum of the<br />

first particle, we can calculate the momentum of the second particle. But since we can make<br />

our choice—as to whether we measure position or momentum—at any time, even after<br />

the collision of the two particles has taken place, it is unreasonable to assume that the<br />

second particle was in any way affected, or interfered with, by the change in the experimental<br />

arrangements resulting from our choice. Accordingly, we can calculate, with any<br />

precision we like, either the position or the momentum of the second particle without<br />

interfering with it; a fact which may be expressed by saying that the second particle ‘has’ both<br />

a precise position and a precise momentum. (Einstein said that both position and<br />

momentum are ‘real’; whereupon he was attacked as ‘reactionary’.) See also the note on<br />

p. 232 and appendices *xi and *xii.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!