25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

188<br />

some structural components of a theory of experience<br />

empirical sequences as chance-like or random of which we hypothetically<br />

assume that they have no frequency limit. But what possible<br />

action could we take in response to this warning? 4 What sort of considerations<br />

or conjectures about the possible convergence or<br />

divergence of empirical sequences should we indulge in or abstain<br />

from, in view of this warning, seeing that criteria of convergence are<br />

no more applicable to them than are criteria of divergence? All these<br />

embarrassing questions 5 disappear once the axiom of convergence has<br />

been got rid of.<br />

Our <strong>logic</strong>al analysis thus makes transparent both the form and the<br />

function of the various partial requirements of the system, and shows<br />

what reasons tell against the axiom of randomness and in favour of the<br />

requirement of uniqueness. Meanwhile the problem of decidability<br />

seems to be growing ever more menacing. And although we are not<br />

obliged to call our requirements (or axioms) ‘meaningless’, 6 it looks<br />

as if we were compelled to describe them as non-empirical. But does<br />

not this description of probability statements—no matter what words<br />

we use to express it—contradict the main idea of our approach?<br />

67 A PROBABILISTIC SYSTEM OF<br />

SPECULATIVE METAPHYSICS<br />

The most important use of probability statements in physics is this:<br />

certain physical regularities or observable physical effects are<br />

4 Both the axiom of randomness and the axiom of uniqueness can properly be regarded<br />

as such (intensional) warnings. For example, the axiom of randomness cautions us not to<br />

treat sequences as random if we suppose (no matter on what grounds) that certain<br />

gambling systems will be successful for them. The axiom of uniqueness cautions us<br />

not to attribute a probability q (with q ≠ p) to a sequence which we suppose can be<br />

approximately described by means of the hypothesis that its probability equals p.<br />

5 Similar misgivings made Schlick object to the limit axiom (Die Naturwissenschaften 19,<br />

1931, p. 158).<br />

6 Here the positivist would have to recognize a whole hierarchy of ‘meaninglessnesses’.<br />

To him, non-verifiable natural laws appear ‘meaningless’ (cf. section 6, and quotations in<br />

notes 1 and 2), and thus still more so probability hypotheses, which are neither verifiable<br />

nor falsifiable. Of our axioms, the axiom of uniqueness, which is not extensionally<br />

significant, would be more meaningless than the meaningless axiom of irregularity,<br />

which at least has extensional consequences. Still more meaningless would be the limit<br />

axiom, since it is not even intensionally significant.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!