25.01.2013 Views

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

popper-logic-scientific-discovery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

182<br />

some structural components of a theory of experience<br />

contradict the estimate. In fact, we must expect it to occur: this is a<br />

consequence of our estimate. The hope that the calculable rarity of any<br />

such segment will be a means of falsifying the probability estimate<br />

proves illusory, since even a frequent occurrence of a long and greatly<br />

deviating segment may always be said to be nothing but one occurrence<br />

of an even longer and more greatly deviating segment. Thus there<br />

are no sequences of events, given to us extensionally, and therefore no<br />

finite n-tuple of basic statements, which could falsify a probability<br />

statement.<br />

Only an infinite sequence of events—defined intensionally by a<br />

rule—could contradict a probability estimate. But this means, in view<br />

of the considerations set forth in section 38 (cf. section 43), that probability<br />

hypotheses are unfalsifiable because their dimension is infinite.<br />

We should therefore really describe them as empirically uninformative,<br />

as void of empirical content. 1<br />

Yet any such view is clearly unacceptable in face of the successes which<br />

physics has achieved with predictions obtained from hypothetical<br />

estimates of probabilities. (This is the same argument as has been used<br />

here much earlier against the interpretation of probability statements as<br />

tautologies by the subjective theory.) Many of these estimates are not<br />

inferior in <strong>scientific</strong> significance to any other physical hypothesis (for<br />

example, to one of a determinist character). And a physicist is usually<br />

quite well able to decide whether he may for the time being accept<br />

some particular probability hypothesis as ‘empirically confirmed’, or<br />

whether he ought to reject it as ‘practically falsified’, i.e., as useless for<br />

purposes of prediction. It is fairly clear that this ‘practical falsification’<br />

can be obtained only through a methodo<strong>logic</strong>al decision to regard<br />

highly improbable events as ruled out—as prohibited. But with what<br />

right can they be so regarded? Where are we to draw the line? Where<br />

does this ‘high improbability’ begin?<br />

Since there can be no doubt, from a purely <strong>logic</strong>al point of view,<br />

about the fact that probability statements cannot be falsified, the<br />

equally indubitable fact that we use them empirically must appear<br />

as a fatal blow to my basic ideas on method which depend crucially<br />

1 But not as void of ‘<strong>logic</strong>al content’ (cf. section 35); for clearly, not every frequency<br />

hypothesis holds tauto<strong>logic</strong>ally for every sequence.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!