01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The satisfaction theory 103<br />

I believe that the contrast between (19a) <strong>and</strong> (24) is of considerable<br />

interest, because it will present a problem to practically any theory which<br />

claims that the inference from (19a) to (19c) is mediated by the<br />

presupposition in (19b). As the following examples show, this contrast is<br />

produced not only by it-clefts but by other presuppositional expressions as<br />

well:<br />

(26) a. If Barney is sensible, then he will stop smoking.<br />

b. Fred knows that if Barney is sensible, then he is a habitual<br />

smoker.<br />

c. Barney is sensible - —> Barney is a habitual smoker<br />

d. Barney is a habitual smoker.<br />

(27) a. If Julius had canard a l'orange, 1'orange, then what his wife ate was<br />

potato chips.<br />

b. Fred knows that if Julius had canard a l'orange, 1'orange, then his wife<br />

ate something (too).<br />

c. Julius had canard a l'orange 1'orange - —> Julius's wife ate something<br />

d. Julius's wife ate something.<br />

(28) a. If Betty is married, then Wilma's husb<strong>and</strong> should be more<br />

discreet.<br />

b. Fred knows that if Betty is married, then Wilma has a husb<strong>and</strong><br />

(too).<br />

c. Betty is married - —> Wilma has a husb<strong>and</strong><br />

d. Wilma has a husb<strong>and</strong>.<br />

Intuitively, we would infer from an utterance of any of the (a) sentences in<br />

(26)-(28) that the speaker takes the corresponding (d) sentence to be true as<br />

well; in (26a) this presupposition is triggered by the aspectual verb, in (27a)<br />

by the w/z-cleft, wh-cleft, <strong>and</strong> in (28a) by the definite NP Wilma's husb<strong>and</strong>. In contrast,<br />

these inferences would not normally follow from the (b) sentences. However,<br />

the satisfaction theory predicts that, in each of these cases, the (a) <strong>and</strong> (b)<br />

sentences have the same presupposition, viz. (c),( <strong>and</strong> that in the first case it<br />

is strenghtened to (d). Why is this presupposition strengthened in the <strong>for</strong>mer<br />

case but not in the latter Clearly, this is bound to be an embarrassing<br />

question not only to theories that adopt the argument from truthfunctionality,<br />

truth-<br />

but to virtually any attempt at dealing with the proviso<br />

problem.<br />

The problem exemplified by (26)-(28) is unlikely to go away if we adopt an<br />

alternative analysis of conditionals. Thus far we have construed if. . ... . then

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!