01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Presupposition 13<br />

that requires a missing presupposition, <strong>and</strong> straightway that<br />

presupposition springs into existence, making what you said<br />

acceptable after all. (Lewis 1979: 339)<br />

This is misleading, to the say the least. 6 Contrary to what Lewis maintains, it<br />

is perfectly easy to say something that is unacceptable <strong>for</strong> lack of required<br />

presuppositions. For example, if in the situation discussed above I had said<br />

(28) instead of (26), my audience would not have let it st<strong>and</strong>, <strong>for</strong> obvious<br />

reasons.<br />

(28) I'm sorry I'm late, my chariot broke down.<br />

If speakers often get away with presupposing something that is not shared<br />

knowledge, it is because they have a finely developed sense <strong>for</strong> what<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation can or cannot be conveyed in this manner. It is not because<br />

accommodation is a rule that is applied by default or even automatically.<br />

Karttunen, too, had the notion of accommodation some years be<strong>for</strong>e<br />

Lewis gave it its name. Karttunen gives the following examples (1974:191): 191):<br />

(29) a. We regret that children cannot accompany their parents to<br />

commencement exercises.<br />

b. There are almost no misprints in this book.<br />

c. John lives in the third brick house down the street from the post<br />

office.<br />

d. It has been pointed out that there are counterexamples to my<br />

theory.<br />

The italicized expressions trigger presuppositions that can be interpreted by<br />

way of accommodation. In (29a), <strong>for</strong> instance, the factive verb regret<br />

triggers the presupposition that children cannot accompany their parents to<br />

commencement exercises, <strong>and</strong> it is this clear that this sentence may be used<br />

felicitously in a context in which the presupposition is not yet part of the<br />

common ground. In fact, a construction like this will often be preferred to<br />

a straigh<strong>for</strong>ward assertion like (30), which may sound too blunt:<br />

(30) Children cannot accompany their parents to commencement<br />

exercises.<br />

Accommodation is often described as a repair strategy. This is not the way<br />

Stalnaker puts it, but that is because he prefers to take the speaker's point of<br />

6<br />

6 To be fair to Lewis it must be noted that he adds as a parenthesis that 'at least, that is what<br />

happens if your conversational partners tacitly acquiesce'. If in the subsequent literature this<br />

crucial rider was sometimes <strong>for</strong>gotten, it is not entirely Lewis's fault, although he is to blame <strong>for</strong><br />

de-emphasizing it.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!