01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CHAPTER 6<br />

Modals<br />

As it st<strong>and</strong>s, the binding theory does not account <strong>for</strong> (la), although it does<br />

offer an explanation <strong>for</strong> (lb): (Ib):<br />

(1) a. Maybe Barney owns a Chevrolet <strong>and</strong> maybe he keeps it<br />

hidden somewhere.<br />

b. Maybe Barney owns a Chevrolet <strong>and</strong> maybe he keeps his<br />

Chevrolet hidden somewhere.<br />

The presupposition triggered by his Chevrolet in (Ib) (lb) cannot be bound, <strong>and</strong><br />

will there<strong>for</strong>e have to be accommodated, <strong>and</strong> since global accommodation<br />

would violate Gricean constraints on interpretation, it will be accommodated<br />

locally. This procedure yields a reading that is intuitively correct but it does<br />

not work <strong>for</strong> (la), because even if the presupposition triggered by the<br />

pronoun could be accommodated, there is nothing to prevent global<br />

accommodation in this case, <strong>and</strong> even if the presupposition were<br />

accommodated locally, we would still not obtain the correct reading <strong>for</strong> this<br />

sentence, which should come out equivalent to (Ib). (lb).<br />

If the accommodation account does not work <strong>for</strong> (la), there is good reason<br />

to suspect that it shouldn't apply to (Ib), (lb), either. This suspicion is<br />

strengthened by the intuition that in (la) as well as in (Ib), (lb), the second modal<br />

somehow picks up <strong>and</strong> extends the hypothetical context created by the first,<br />

<strong>and</strong> that the reference marker introduced by the indefinite noun phrase in<br />

the first conjunct should be accessible whenever this context is being<br />

extended, which is what the second conjunct does. Many of the authors who<br />

have discussed this type of example, beginning with Karttunen (1976),<br />

appear to share this intuition, which implies that the personal pronoun it in<br />

(la) <strong>and</strong> the definite noun phrase his Chevrolet in (Ib) (lb) are bound rather than<br />

accommodated.<br />

The phenomenon illustrated by (la) has come to be known under the<br />

name of 'modal subordination', which was coined by Roberts (1987, 1989,<br />

1996). Initially Roberts restricted the notion of modal subordination to<br />

anaphoric pronouns, but as she observes in her 1996 paper, the same<br />

phenomenon occurs with all sorts of presuppositional expressions, as (Ib) (lb)<br />

illustrates (this type of example was discussed already by Gazdar 1979). We<br />

PRESUPPOSITIONS AND PRONOUNS, Current Research in the <strong>Semantics</strong>/Pragmatics Interface, Vol. 3<br />

B. Geurts - © 1999 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!