01.02.2015 Views

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

Presuppositions and Pronouns - Nijmegen Centre for Semantics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Presupposition 17<br />

conditionals have the same projection profile because both types of<br />

statement affect their contexts in two consecutive steps.<br />

This is Stalnaker's pragmatic account of presupposition projection. Like<br />

the wheel, it is based on a simple but compelling idea, <strong>and</strong> it is just too good<br />

to be wrong. There are two aspects of Stalnaker's theory that I want to<br />

emphasize. First, it is a pragmatic theory. Sentences don't change contexts;<br />

they don't do anything. It is speakers who employ sentences to change the<br />

context. This distinction is an important one because the past two decades<br />

have witnessed the rise of a paradigm, inaugurated by Heim's (1982, 1983)<br />

work on anaphora <strong>and</strong> presupposition, which incorporates Stalnaker's<br />

insights by casting them in a semantical mould. These developments will be<br />

discussed at length in later chapters, but I should like to note be<strong>for</strong>eh<strong>and</strong><br />

that, although they were inspired by Stalnaker's work, they depart from his<br />

intentions in a quite radical way. By contrast, the theory that I advocate<br />

remains loyal to Stalnaker's concept of speaker presupposition.<br />

The second point that bears emphasizing is that on Stalnaker's account of<br />

presupposition projection, it need not be assumed that presuppositions are<br />

cancellable. We have seen that a presupposition triggered in the consequent<br />

of a conditional seems to disappear if it is entailed by the antecedent, <strong>and</strong> it<br />

is sometimes said that in such cases presuppositions are eliminated or<br />

cancelled. In some theories of projection this is not merely a manner of<br />

speaking, since they require that presuppositions are literally cancellable. 9<br />

On Stalnaker's account presuppositions are never cancelled. If they<br />

sometimes seem to disappear it is because they may be satisfied by a local<br />

context. Thus, if q> cp entails X, %, the presupposition triggered in 'if q> (p then ",{X}' X|/{%}'<br />

seems to 'disappear' because in the intermediate context in which ",{X} \\f{%} is<br />

evaluated it is already given that X % is is true. Nowadays it it is is widely, though not<br />

universally, agreed that this view is correct, <strong>and</strong> that, strictly speaking,<br />

presuppositions can never be cancelled.<br />

In the following chapters, I present a theory which is based on Stalnaker's<br />

insight that presuppositions are pieces of in<strong>for</strong>mation which are taken to be<br />

given, either in the main context or in some local context. However, what I<br />

have to offer is not just a theory of presupposition but a unified account of<br />

presupposition <strong>and</strong> anaphora. That is to say, in the following I will adopt <strong>and</strong><br />

elaborate upon van der S<strong>and</strong>t's (1987, 1992) hypothesis that anaphora is a<br />

species of presupposition. This hypothesis will be discussed at some length in<br />

the next chapter; the following examples merely are to give it some initial<br />

plausibility:<br />

(36) a. Fred cheated at the exam, <strong>and</strong> he regrets {it/that he cheated at<br />

the exam}.<br />

9<br />

9 Theories that require presuppositions to be defeasible have been proposed by Karttunen<br />

(1973a), Gazdar (1979), van der S<strong>and</strong>t (1988), Mercer (1992), <strong>and</strong> many others.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!